Cardinality: Difference between revisions
Undid revision 1296067134 by D.Lazard (talk) I will. Please allow time for discussion before removing half the article. |
Reverted 1 edit by Farkle Griffen (talk): Please, discuss instead of edit-warring; the only things that I have removed are trivia that do not belong to this article |
||
Line 13: | Line 13: | ||
Cardinalities are represented with [[cardinal number]]s, which are specific sets of a given cardinality, which have been chosen once for all. Some infinite cardinalities have been given a specific name, such as {{tmath|\aleph_0}} for the cardinality of the natural numbers and {{tmath|\mathfrak c}}, the [[cardinality of the continuum]], for the cardinality of the real numbers. |
Cardinalities are represented with [[cardinal number]]s, which are specific sets of a given cardinality, which have been chosen once for all. Some infinite cardinalities have been given a specific name, such as {{tmath|\aleph_0}} for the cardinality of the natural numbers and {{tmath|\mathfrak c}}, the [[cardinality of the continuum]], for the cardinality of the real numbers. |
||
== |
==Basics== |
||
===Finite cardinalities=== |
|||
In English, the term ''cardinality'' originates from the [[Post-Classical Latin language|post-classical Latin]] ''cardinalis'', meaning "principal" or "chief", which derives from ''cardo'', a noun meaning "hinge". In Latin, ''cardo'' referred to something central or pivotal, both literally and metaphorically. This concept of centrality passed into [[medieval Latin]] and then into English, where ''cardinal'' came to describe things considered to be, in some sense, fundamental, such as ''[[cardinal virtues]]'', ''[[cardinal sins]]'', ''[[cardinal directions]]'', and (in the grammatical sense) ''[[Cardinal numbers (linguistics)|cardinal numbers]].<ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "cardinal (adj.), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/1490074521.</ref>''<ref>Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinal," [[Etymonline]], Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinal.</ref> The last of which referred to numbers used for counting (e.g., one, two, three),<ref>''[[Oxford English Dictionary]]'', "cardinal number (''n.''), sense 1," July 2023, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/3193437451.</ref> as opposed to ''[[Ordinal numbers (linguistics)|ordinal numbers]]'', which express order (e.g., first, second, third),<ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "ordinal (n.2)," June 2024, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/6032173309.</ref> and [[Nominal number|''nominal numbers'']] used for labeling without meaning (e.g., [[jersey numbers]] and [[serial numbers]]).<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Woodin |first1=Greg |last2=Winter |first2=Bodo |year=2024 |title=Numbers in Context: Cardinals, Ordinals, and Nominals in American English |journal=Cognitive Science |volume=48 |doi=10.1111/cogs.13471 |pmc=11475258 |pmid=38895756 |doi-access=free |article-number=e13471 |number=6}}</ref> |
|||
Given a [[finite set]], its ''cardinality'' is what is commonly called its ''number of elements''. |
|||
The standard way to compute this number of elements is by [[counting]], that is, by labelling the set elements by the first [[natural number]]s, with no gap and no repetition. Mathematically, counting amounts to construct a [[bijective function]] from the first natural numbers to the set to be counted. |
|||
In mathematics, the notion of cardinality was first introduced by [[Georg Cantor]] in the late 19th century, wherein he used the used the term ''Mächtigkeit'', which may be translated as "magnitude" or "power", though Cantor credited the term to a work by [[Jakob Steiner]] on [[projective geometry]].<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Ferreirós |first=José |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3 |title=Labyrinth of Thought |date=2007 |publisher=[[Birkhäuser]] |isbn=978-3-7643-8349-7 |edition=2nd |location=Basel |pages=24 |doi=10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3}}</ref><ref name=":3">{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |author-link=Georg Cantor |date=1932 |editor-last=Zermelo |editor-first=Ernst |editor-link=Ernst Zermelo |title=Gesammelte Abhandlungen |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2 |journal=Springer |location=Berlin |pages=151 |doi=10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2 |isbn=978-3-662-00254-4}}</ref><ref name=":4">{{Cite book |last=Steiner |first=Jacob |url=https://archive.org/details/bub_gb_jCgPAAAAQAAJ/ |title=Vorlesungen über synthetische Geometrie / 1 Die Theorie der Kegelschnitte in elementarer Form |date=1867 |publisher=Leipzig : Teubner |others=Ghent University}}</ref> The terms ''cardinality'' and ''cardinal number'' were eventually adopted from the grammatical sense, and later translations would use these terms.<ref>Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinality," [[Etymonline]], Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinality.</ref><ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "cardinality (n.2), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/5444748676.</ref> |
|||
The ''number of elements'' of a finite set is the largest natural number reached by counting its elements. So, a set {{tmath|S}} has {{tmath|n}} elements if there is a bijective function from the set <math>\{1, 2, \ldots,n\} </math> to {{tmath|S}}. One says that the ''cardinality'' of {{tmath|S}} |
|||
==History== |
|||
is {{tmath|n}}. If the counting process never finishes, one has an ''infinite set''. |
|||
A [[proof by induction]] is needed for proving that the result of counting does not depend on the order in which the elements are counted. This is expressed by the fact that, if {{tmath|m<n}} there is no injective function, and thus no bijective function, from <math>\{1, 2, \ldots,n\}</math> to <math>\{1, 2, \ldots,m\}.</math> A variant of this property is often referred to as the [[pigeonhole principle]]. |
|||
=== Prehistory === |
|||
{{Further|Tally marks#Early history| History of ancient numeral systems}} |
|||
The latter poperty is equivalent with the fact that , if {{tmath|m<n}} there is no [[surjective function]] from <math>\{1, 2, \ldots,m\}</math> to <math>\{1, 2, \ldots,n\}.</math> This means that for finite sets, the fifth [[Euclid's common notion]] applies, which states that ''"the whole is greater than the part".'' This principle is not valid for infinite sets, and this is presumably the main reason for which most mathematicians were reluctant to study infinite sets, before the 20th century (see [[Galileo's paradox]]). |
|||
A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.<ref>Cepelewicz, Jordana ''[https://www.quantamagazine.org/animals-can-count-and-use-zero-how-far-does-their-number-sense-go-20210809/ Animals Count and Use Zero. How Far Does Their Number Sense Go?]'', [[Quanta Magazine|Quanta]], August 9, 2021</ref> Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as {{val|40,000}} years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://mathtimeline.weebly.com/early-human-counting-tools.html|title=Early Human Counting Tools|website=Math Timeline|access-date=2018-04-26}}</ref> The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian [[History of mathematics|mathematics]] and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.<ref>Duncan J. Melville (2003). [http://it.stlawu.edu/~dmelvill/mesomath/3Mill/chronology.html Third Millennium Chronology] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180707213616/http://it.stlawu.edu/~dmelvill/mesomath/3Mill/chronology.html |date=2018-07-07 }}, ''Third Millennium Mathematics''. [[St. Lawrence University]].</ref> |
|||
=== |
=== General case === |
||
[[File:AristotlesWheelLabeledDiagram.svg|thumb|252x252px|Diagram of Aristotle's wheel as described in ''Mechanica''.]] |
|||
From the 6th century BCE, the writings of [[Greek philosophers]], such as [[Anaximander]], show hints of comparing infinite sets or shapes. While the Greeks considered notions of infinity, they viewed it as paradoxical and imperfect (cf. ''[[Zeno's paradoxes]]''), often associating good and evil with finite and infinite.<ref name="Allen22">{{Cite web |last=Allen |first=Donald |date=2003 |title=The History of Infinity |url=https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200801202539/https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |archive-date=August 1, 2020 |access-date=Nov 15, 2019 |website=Texas A&M Mathematics}}</ref> [[Aristotle]] distinguished between the notions of [[actual infinity]] and potential infinity, arguing that Greek mathematicians understood the difference, and that they "do not need the [actual] infinite and do not use it."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Allen |first1=Reginald E. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3bNw_OmGNwYC&pg=PA256 |title=Plato's Parmenides |publisher=Yale University Press |year=1998 |isbn=9780300138030 |series=The Dialogues of Plato |volume=4 |location=New Haven |page=256 |oclc=47008500}}</ref> The greek notion of number (''αριθμός'', ''arithmos'') was used exclusively for a definite number of definite objects (i.e. finite numbers).<ref>{{Cite book |last=Klein |first=Jacob |author-link=Jacob Klein (philosopher) |url=http://archive.org/details/jacob-klein-greek-mathematical-thought-and-the-origin-of-algebra |title=Greek Mathematical Thought And The Origin Of Algebra |date=1992 |publisher=[[Dover Publications]] |isbn=0-486-27289-3 |location=New York |page=46 |translator-last=Brann |translator-first=Eva |lccn=92-20992 |orig-year=1934 |translator-link=Eva Brann}}</ref> This would be codified in [[Euclid's Elements|Euclid's ''Elements'']], where the [[Euclidean geometry#common notions|fifth common notion]] states "The whole is greater than the part", often called the ''Euclidean principle''. This principle would be the dominating philosophy in mathematics until the 19th century.<ref name="Allen22" /><ref>{{Cite book |last=Mayberry |first=John P. |url=http://archive.org/details/foundationsofmat0000john |title=Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets |date=2011 |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |isbn=978-0-521-17271-4 |series=Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications |issn=0953-4806}}</ref> |
|||
Cardinalities, like natural numbers, are difficult to define formally, and this is by their basic properties that there are best introduced. Therefore, in this section, the cardinality of a set is not defined as a value, but only the comparison between cardinalities (equality and greater than) is defined and studied. (This is to compare with the natural numbers for which operations and ordering are defined a long time before any proper definition of the concept.) |
|||
Around the 4th century BCE, [[Jaina mathematics]] would be the first to discuss different sizes of infinity. They defined three major classes of number: enumerable (finite numbers), unenumerable (''asamkhyata'', roughly, [[#Countable sets|countably infinite]]), and infinite (''ananta''). Then they had five classes of infinite numbers: infinite in one direction, infinite in both directions, infinite in area, infinite everywhere, and infinite perpetually.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Joseph |first=George Gheverghese |author-link=George Gheverghese Joseph |url=https://press.princeton.edu/books/paperback/9780691135267/the-crest-of-the-peacock |title=The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics |date=Oct 24, 2010 |publisher=[[Princeton University Press]] |isbn=978-0-691-13526-7 |edition=3rd |location=Princeton, New Jersey |pages=349-351 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/crest-of-the-peacock-joseph-george-gheverghese |archive-date=2024-08-05}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |last=O'Connor |first=John J. |last2=Robertson |first2=Edmund F. |author-link2=E. F. Robertson |date=2000 |title=MacTutor{{snd}}Jaina mathematics |url=https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/HistTopics/Jaina_mathematics/ |access-date=2025-06-09 |website=[[MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive]] |language=en |via=[[University of St Andrews]], Scotland}}</ref> |
|||
The cardinality of a finite set {{tmath|S}} is a natural number, the numbers of its elements, which is commonly denoted {{math|{{abs|''S''}}}} or {{tmath|\#S}}.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Cardinality {{!}} Brilliant Math & Science Wiki |url=https://brilliant.org/wiki/cardinality/ |access-date=2020-08-23 |website=brilliant.org |language=en-us}}</ref> These notations are also used for infinite sets, although <math>\operatorname{card}(S)</math> seems more common in the infinite case.{{cn}} |
|||
One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded in [[Mechanics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's ''Mechanics'']] ({{Circa|350 BCE}}), known as [[Aristotle's wheel paradox]]. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as two [[concentric circles]]. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: the [[circumference]] of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Drabkin |first=Israel E. |date=1950 |title=Aristotle's Wheel: Notes on the History of a Paradox |journal=Osiris |volume=9 |pages=162–198 |doi=10.1086/368528 |jstor=301848 |s2cid=144387607}}</ref> Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.<ref name="Allen22" /> |
|||
=== |
==== Equinumerosity ==== |
||
{{Multiple image |
|||
| direction = horizontal |
|||
| image1 = Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) RMG BHC2700.tiff |
|||
| image2 = Bernard Bolzano.jpg |
|||
| total_width = 350 |
|||
| footer = Portrait of [[Galileo Galilei]], circa 1640 (left). Portrait of [[Bernard Bolzano]] 1781–1848 (right). |
|||
}} |
|||
[[Galileo Galilei]] presented what was later coined [[Galileo's paradox]] in his book ''[[Two New Sciences]]'' (1638), where he attempts to show that infinite quantities cannot be called greater or less than one another. He presents the paradox roughly as follows: a [[square number]] is one which is the product of another number with itself, such as 4 and 9, which are the squares of 2 and 3, respectively. Then the [[square root]] of a square number is that multiplicand. He then notes that there are as many square numbers as there are square roots, since every square has its own root and every root its own square, while no square has more than one root and no root more than one square. But there are as many square roots as there are numbers, since every number is the square root of some square. He denied that this was fundamentally contradictory, however, he concluded that this meant we could not compare the sizes of infinite sets, missing the opportunity to discover cardinality.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Galilei |first=Galileo |author-link=Galileo Galilei |url=https://dn790007.ca.archive.org/0/items/dialoguesconcern00galiuoft/dialoguesconcern00galiuoft.pdf |title=Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences |publisher=[[The Macmillan Company]] |year=1914 |location=New York |pages=31–33 |language=en |translator-last=Crew |translator-first=Henry |orig-year=1638 |translator-last2=De Salvio |translator-first2=Alfonso}}</ref> |
|||
Two sets have the ''same cardinality'' or are ''equinumerous'' if there exists a [[bijection]] or ''one-to-one correspondence'' between them. For example, the [[integer]]s and the [[even integers]] have the same cardinality, since multiplication and division by 2 provide bijection between them. |
|||
[[Bernard Bolzano]]'s ''[[Paradoxes of the Infinite]]'' (''Paradoxien des Unendlichen'', 1851) is often considered the first systematic attempt to introduce the concept of sets into [[mathematical analysis]]. In this work, Bolzano defended the notion of [[actual infinity]], examined various properties of infinite collections, including an early formulation of what would later be recognized as one-to-one correspondence between infinite sets, and proposed to base mathematics on a notion similar to sets. He discussed examples such as the pairing between the [[Interval (mathematics)|intervals]] <math>[0,5]</math> and <math>[0,12]</math> by the relation <math>5y = 12x.</math> Bolzano also revisited and extended Galileo's paradox. However, he too resisted saying that these sets were, in that sense, the same size. Thus, while ''Paradoxes of the Infinite'' anticipated several ideas central to later set theory, the work had little influence on contemporary mathematics, in part due to its [[posthumous publication]] and limited circulation.<ref>{{Citation |last=Ferreirós |first=José |title=The Early Development of Set Theory |date=2024 |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/settheory-early/ |access-date=2025-01-04 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210512135148/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/settheory-early/ |archive-date=2021-05-12 |url-status=live |edition=Winter 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Bolzano |first=Bernard |title=Einleitung zur Größenlehre und erste Begriffe der allgemeinen Größenlehre |volume=II, A, 7 |page=152 |year=1975 |editor-last=Berg |editor-first=Jan |series=Bernard-Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe, edited by Eduard Winter et al. |location=Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt |publisher=Friedrich Frommann Verlag |isbn=3-7728-0466-7 |author-link=Bernard Bolzano}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Bolzano |first=Bernard |url=https://archive.org/details/dli.ernet.503861/ |title=Paradoxes Of The Infinite |date=1950 |publisher=Routledge and Kegan Paul |location=London |translator-last=Prihonsky |translator-first=Fr.}}</ref> |
|||
The equinumerosity of two sets {{tmath|A}} and {{tmath|B}} is denoted |
|||
Other, more minor contributions include [[David Hume]] in ''[[A Treatise of Human Nature]]'' (1739), who said ''"When two numbers are so combined, as that the one has always a unit answering to every unit of the other, we pronounce them equal",<ref>{{cite book |last=Hume |first=David |date=1739–1740 |title=A Treatise of Human Nature |chapter=Part III. Of Knowledge and Probability: Sect. I. Of Knowledge |chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0021 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>'' now called ''[[Hume's principle]]'', which was used extensively by [[Gottlob Frege]] later during the rise of set theory.<ref>{{cite book |last=Frege |first=Gottlob |date=1884 |title=Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik |chapter=IV. Der Begriff der Anzahl § 63. Die Möglichkeit der eindeutigen Zuordnung als solches. Logisches Bedenken, dass die Gleichheit für diesen Fall besonders erklärt wird |quote=§63. Ein solches Mittel nennt schon Hume: »Wenn zwei Zahlen so combinirt werden, dass die eine immer eine Einheit hat, die jeder Einheit der andern entspricht, so geben wir sie als gleich an.« |chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/48312/pg48312-images.html#para_63 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref> [[Jakob Steiner]], whom [[Georg Cantor]] credits the original term, ''Mächtigkeit'', for cardinality (1867).<ref name=":2" /><ref name=":3" /><ref name=":4" /> [[Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet]] is commonly credited for being the first to explicitly formulate the [[pigeonhole principle]] in 1834,<ref>Jeff Miller, Peter Flor, Gunnar Berg, and Julio González Cabillón. "[http://jeff560.tripod.com/p.html Pigeonhole principle]". In Jeff Miller (ed.) ''[http://jeff560.tripod.com/mathword.html Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics]''. Electronic document, retrieved November 11, 2006</ref> though it was used at least two centuries earlier by [[Jean Leurechon]] in 1624.<ref name="leurechon">{{cite journal |last1=Rittaud |first1=Benoît |last2=Heeffer |first2=Albrecht |year=2014 |title=The pigeonhole principle, two centuries before Dirichlet |url=https://biblio.ugent.be/publication/4115264 |journal=The Mathematical Intelligencer |volume=36 |issue=2 |pages=27–29 |doi=10.1007/s00283-013-9389-1 |mr=3207654 |s2cid=44193229 |hdl-access=free |hdl=1854/LU-4115264}}</ref> |
|||
:<math>\operatorname{card}(A)=\operatorname{card}(B).</math> |
|||
For any three sets {{tmath|A}}, {{tmath|B}}, and {{tmath|C}}, one has |
|||
=== Early set theory === |
|||
* {{tmath|1=\operatorname{card}(A) = \operatorname{card}(A)\qquad}} (reflexitivity), |
|||
* {{tmath|1=\operatorname{card}(A) = \operatorname{card}(B) \implies \operatorname{card}(B) = \operatorname{card}(A)\qquad}} (symmetry), |
|||
* {{tmath|1=\operatorname{card}(A) = \operatorname{card}(B)}} and {{tmath|1=\operatorname{card}(B) = \operatorname{card}(C) \implies \operatorname{card}(A) = \operatorname{card}(C) \qquad}} (transitivity). |
|||
This results immediately from the fact that the [[identity function]], the [[inverse function]] of a bijective function, and the [[function composition|composition]] of two bijective functions are all bijective. This means that equinumerosity is an [[equivalence relation]] on the subsets of a given set.{{efn|The common definition of an equvalence relation supposes that the elements to be compared belong to a set. Since there is no set of all sets, for talking of equinumerosity as an equivalence relation, one needs to change the definition of an equivalence relation by allowing [[proper class]]es.}} |
|||
See below for various examples. |
|||
==== Georg Cantor ==== |
|||
[[File:Georg_Cantor3.jpg|alt=refer to caption|thumb|339x339px|[[Georg Cantor]], {{spaces|4|hair}}{{circa}} 1870]] |
|||
The concept of cardinality, as a formal measure of the size of a set, emerged nearly fully formed in the work of Georg Cantor during the 1870s and 1880s, in the context of [[mathematical analysis]]. In a series of papers beginning with ''[[Cantor's first set theory article|On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers]]'' (1874),<ref>{{Citation |last=Cantor |first=Herrn |title=Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen |date=1984 |work=Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfaltigkeiten: Arbeiten zur Mengenlehre aus den Jahren 1872–1884 |series=Teubner-Archiv zur Mathematik |volume=2 |pages=19–24 |editor-last=Cantor |editor-first=Georg |orig-date=1874 |url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-7091-9516-1_2 |access-date=2025-05-24 |place=Vienna |publisher=Springer |language=de |doi=10.1007/978-3-7091-9516-1_2 |isbn=978-3-7091-9516-1}}</ref> Cantor introduced the idea of comparing the sizes of infinite sets, through the notion of one-to-one correspondence. He showed that the set of [[real numbers]] was, in this sense, strictly larger than the set of natural numbers [[Cantor's first set theory article#Second theorem|using a nested intervals argument]]. This result was later refined into the more widely known [[Cantor's diagonal argument|diagonal argument]] of 1891, published in ''Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,''<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1890 |title=Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigketislehre. |url=https://eudml.org/doc/144383 |journal=Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung |volume=1 |pages=72–78 |issn=0012-0456}}</ref> where he also proved the more general result (now called [[Cantor's Theorem]]) that the [[power set]] of any set is strictly larger than the set itself. |
|||
==== Partial order ==== |
|||
Cantor introduced the notion [[cardinal numbers]] in terms of [[ordinal numbers]]. He viewed cardinal numbers as an abstraction of sets, introduced the notations, where, for a given set <math display="inline">M</math>, the [[order type]] of that set was written <math display="inline">\overline{M}</math>, and the cardinal number was <span style="border-top: 3px double;"><math display="inline">M</math></span>, a double abstraction. He also introduced the [[#Aleph numbers|Aleph sequence]] for infinite cardinal numbers. These notations appeared in correspondence and were formalized in his later writings, particularly the series ''Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre'' (1895{{En dash}}1897).<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1895-11-01 |title=Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre |url=https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/BF02124929 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=de |volume=46 |issue=4 |pages=481–512 |doi=10.1007/BF02124929 |issn=1432-1807}}</ref> In these works, Cantor developed an [[Cardinal arithmetic|arithmetic of cardinal numbers]], defining addition, multiplication, and exponentiation of cardinal numbers based on set-theoretic constructions. This led to the formulation of the [[Continuum Hypothesis]] (CH), the proposition that no set has cardinality strictly between <math>\aleph_0</math> and the [[cardinality of the continuum]], that is <math>|\R| = \aleph_1</math>. Cantor was unable to resolve CH and left it as an [[open problem]]. |
|||
One says that the cardinality of a set {{tmath|A}} is less than or equal to the cardinality of {{tmath|B}}, denoted |
|||
==== Other contributors ==== |
|||
:<math>\operatorname{card}(A) \le \operatorname{card} (B),</math> |
|||
Parallel to Cantor’s development, [[Richard Dedekind]] independently formulated [[Dedekind-infinite set|a definition of infinite set]] as one that can be placed in bijection with a proper subset of itself, which was shown to be equivalent with Cantor’s definition of cardinality (given the [[axiom of choice]]). Dedekind’s ''[[Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?]]'' (1888) emphasized structural properties over extensional definitions, and supported the bijective formulation of size and number. Dedekind was in correspondence with Cantor during the development of set theory; he supplied Cantor with a proof of the countability of the [[algebraic numbers]], and gave feedback and modifications on Cantor's proofs before publishing. |
|||
if there is an [[injective function]] from {{tmath|A}} to {{tmath|B}}. |
|||
This defines a [[partial order]] on cardinalities, since one has |
|||
After Cantor's 1883 proof that all finite-dimensional spaces <math>(\R^n)</math> have the same cardinality,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1883-12-01 |title=Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01446819 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=de |volume=21 |issue=4 |pages=545–591 |doi=10.1007/BF01446819 |issn=1432-1807}}</ref> in 1890, [[Giuseppe Peano]] introduced the [[Peano curve]], which was a more visual proof that the [[unit interval]] <math>[0,1]</math> has the same cardinality as the [[unit square]] on <math>\R^2.</math><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Peano |first=G. |date=1890-03-01 |title=Sur une courbe, qui remplit toute une aire plane |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01199438 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=fr |volume=36 |issue=1 |pages=157–160 |doi=10.1007/BF01199438 |issn=1432-1807 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/PeanoSurUneCurve |archive-date=2018-07-22}}</ref> This created a new area of mathematical analysis studying what is now called [[space-filling curves]].<ref>{{citation |last=Gugenheimer |first=Heinrich Walter |title=Differential Geometry |page=3 |year=1963 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CSYtkV4NTioC&pg=PA |publisher=Courier Dover Publications |isbn=9780486157207}}.</ref> |
|||
* {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(A)\le \operatorname{card}(A)}}, |
|||
* {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(A)\le \operatorname{card}(B)}} and {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(B)\le \operatorname{card}(C)}} imply {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(A)\le \operatorname{card}(C)}} |
|||
* {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(A)\le \operatorname{card}(B)}} and {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(B)\le \operatorname{card}(A)}} inly {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(A) \operatorname{card}(A)}}. |
|||
The two first assertions result from the fact that the identity function and the composition of two injective functions are injective. The third assertion results from [[Schröder–Bernstein theorem]], which asserts that, given an injection from {{tmath|A}} into {{tmath|B}} and an injection from {{tmath|B}} into {{tmath|A}}, one can construct a bijection between {{tmath|A}} and {{tmath|B}}. |
|||
German logician [[Gottlob Frege]] attempted to ground the concepts of number and arithmetic in logic using Cantor's theory of cardinality and [[Hume's principle]] in ''[[Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik]]'' (1884) and the subsequent ''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'' (1893, 1903). Frege defined cardinal numbers as [[equivalence classes]] of sets under equinumerosity. However, Frege's approach to set theory was later shown to be flawed. His approach was eventually reformalized by [[Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation|Bertrand Russell]] and [[Alfred North Whitehead|Alfred Whitehead]] in ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (1910{{En dash}}1913, vol. II){{Sfn|Russell|Whitehead}} using a [[Type theory#History|theory of types]]. Though Russell initially had difficulties understanding Cantor's and Frege’s intuitions of cardinality.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Russell |first=B. |date=1907 |title=On Some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types |url=https://londmathsoc.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29?doi=10.1112%2Fplms%2Fs2-4.1.29 |journal=Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society |language=en |volume=s2-4 |issue=1 |pages=29–53 |doi=10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29 |issn=1460-244X}}</ref> This definition of cardinal numbers is now referred to as the ''Frege-Russell'' definition. |
|||
If the [[axiom of choice]] is assumed, as it is commonly the case in modern mathematics, this partial order is a [[total order]] and a [[well-order]]. |
|||
=== Axiomatic set theory === |
|||
{{Multiple image |
|||
| image1 = Ernst Zermelo 1900s.jpg |
|||
| image2 = Kurt gödel.jpg |
|||
| total_width = 350 |
|||
| footer = [[Ernst Zermelo]] and [[Kurt Gödel]] |
|||
}} |
|||
In 1908, [[Ernst Zermelo]] proposed the first [[axiomatization]] of set theory, now called [[Zermelo set theory]], primarily to support his earlier (1904) proof of the [[Well-ordering theorem]], which showed that all cardinal numbers could be represented as [[#Aleph numbers|Alephs]], though the proof required a controversial principle now known as the [[Axiom of Choice]] (AC). Zermelo's system would later be extended by [[Abraham Fraenkel]] and [[Thoralf Skolem]] in the 1920s to create the standard foundation of set theory, called [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] (ZFC, "C" for the Axiom of Choice). ZFC provided a rigorous, albeit non-[[Categorical theory|categorical]], foundation through which infinite cardinals could be systematically studied while avoiding the [[Paradoxes of set theory|paradoxes of naive set theory]]. |
|||
Without the axiom of choice, one cannot prove that cadinalities are totally ordered. In particular, without the axiom of choice, there may exist [[Dedekind finite set]]s that are infinite; for such a set {{tmath|F}}, one has neither {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(F)\le \operatorname{card}(\N)}} nor {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(\N)\le \operatorname{card}(F)}}. |
|||
In 1940, [[Kurt Gödel]] showed that CH cannot be ''disproved'' from ZF set theory (ZFC without Choice), even if the axiom of choice is adopted, i.e. from ZFC. Gödel's proof shows that both CH and AC hold in the [[constructible universe]], an [[inner model]] of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are (relatively) [[consistent]] with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gödel |first1=Kurt |date=1938 |title=The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |volume=24 |issue=12 |pages=556–557 |bibcode=1938PNAS...24..556G |doi=10.1073/pnas.24.12.556 |pmc=1077160 |pmid=16577857 |doi-access=free}}</ref> In 1963, [[Paul Cohen]] showed that CH cannot be ''proven'' from the ZFC axioms, which showed that CH was [[Independence (mathematical logic)|independent]] from ZFC. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of [[Forcing (mathematics)|forcing]], which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZFC in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the [[Fields Medal]] in 1966 for his proof.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=P. J. |date=1963 |title=THE INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS |url=https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC221287/ |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=50 |issue=6 |pages=1143–1148 |doi=10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=221287 |pmid=16578557}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Cohen |first=Paul Joseph |author-link=Paul Cohen (mathematician) |title=Set theory and the continuum hypothesis |date=2008 |publisher=Dover Publications |isbn=978-0-486-46921-8 |location=Mineola, New York City |orig-date=1966}}</ref> |
|||
==Comparing sets== |
|||
== Countable sets == |
|||
{{main|Countable set}} |
|||
[[File:Aplicación 2 inyectiva sobreyectiva04.svg|thumb|250px|A one-to-one correspondence from '''N''', the set of all non-negative integers, to the set '''E''' of non-negative [[even number]]s. Although '''E''' is a proper subset of '''N''', both sets have the same cardinality.]] |
|||
The basic notions of [[Set (mathematics)|sets]] and [[Function (mathematics)|functions]] are used to develop the concept of cardinality, and technical terms therein are used throughout this article. A [[Set (mathematics)|set]] can be understood as any collection of objects, usually represented with [[curly braces]]. For example, <math>S = \{1,2,3\}</math> specifies a set, called <math>S</math>, which contains the numbers 1, 2, and 3. The symbol <math>\in</math> represents set membership, for example <math>1 \in S</math> says "1 is a member of the set <math>S</math>" which is true by the definition of <math>S</math> above. |
|||
As suggested by the name, a ''countable set'' is a set that can be exhausted by counting its elements, possibly with an endless counting. Such a counting process defines an injective function from the set to the natual numbers. |
|||
A [[Function (mathematics)|function]] is an association that maps elements of one set to the elements of another, often represented with an arrow diagram. For example, the adjacent image depicts a function which maps the set of [[natural numbers]] to the set of [[even numbers]] by multiplying by 2. If a function does not map two elements to the same place, it is called [[injective]]. If a function covers every element in the output space, it is called [[surjective]]. If a function is both injective and surjective, it is called [[bijective]]. (For further clarification, see ''[[Bijection, injection and surjection]]''.) |
|||
So, a countable set is a set {{tmath|S}} such that {{tmath|1=\operatorname {card}(S) \le \operatorname {card}(\N)}}. Thus, a countable set is either a finite set or a ''countably infinite'' set, that is a set such that {{tmath|1=\operatorname {card}(S) = \operatorname {card}(\N)}}. |
|||
===Equinumerosity=== |
|||
{{Main|Equinumerosity}} |
|||
The intuitive property of two sets having the "same size" is that their objects can be paired one-to-one. For example, in [[#top|the image above]], a set of apples is paired with a set of oranges, proving the sets are the same size without referring to these sets' "number of elements" at all. A one-to-one pairing between two sets defines a bijective function between them by mapping each object to its pair. Similarly, a bijection between two sets defines a pairing of their elements by pairing each object with the one it maps to. Therefore, these notions of "pairing" and "bijection" are intuitively equivalent. In fact, it is often the case that functions are defined literally as this set of pairings (see ''{{slink|Function (mathematics)|Formal definition}}''). Thus, the following definition is given: |
|||
Every subset of a countable set is countable. |
|||
Two sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> are said to have the ''same cardinality'' if their elements can be paired one-to-one. That is, if there exists a function <math>f:A \mapsto B</math> which is bijective. This is written as <math>A \sim B,</math> <math>A \approx B,</math> <math>A \equiv B,</math> and eventually <math> |A| = |B| , </math> once <math>|A|</math> has been defined. Alternatively, these sets, <math>A </math> and <math> B,</math> may be said to be ''similar'', ''[[equinumerous]]'', or ''equipotent''. For example, the set <math>E = \{0, 2, 4, 6, \text{...}\}</math> of non-negative [[even number]]s has the same cardinality as the set <math>\N = \{0, 1, 2, 3, \text{...}\}</math> of [[natural numbers]], since the function <math>f(n) = 2n</math> is a bijection from {{tmath|\N}} to {{tmath|E}} (see picture above). |
|||
[[File:Diagonal argument.svg|thumb|Illustration of the proof that the sequences of two natural numbers form a countable set, and that the same is true for the subset of irreducible fractions (in black)]] |
|||
For finite sets {{tmath|A}} and {{tmath|B}}, if ''some'' bijection exists from {{tmath|A}} to {{tmath|B}}, then ''each'' injective or surjective function from {{tmath|A}} to {{tmath|B}} is a bijection. This property is no longer true for infinite {{tmath|A}} and {{tmath|B}}. For example, the function {{tmath|g}} from {{tmath|\N}} to {{tmath|E}}, defined by <math>g(n) = 4n</math> is injective, but not surjective since 2, for instance, is not mapped to, and {{tmath|h}} from {{tmath|\N}} to {{tmath|E}}, defined by <math>h(n) = 2 \operatorname{floor}(n/2)</math> (see: ''[[floor function]]'') is surjective, but not injective, since 0 and 1 for instance both map to 0. Neither {{tmath|g}} nor {{tmath|h}} can challenge <math>|E| = |\N|,</math> which was established by the existence of {{tmath|f}}. |
|||
Many sets that seem to be much larger that the natural numbers are neverthess countable. This is the case, in particular, of the set of all [[finite sequence]]s of natural numbers. This can be proven by ordering these sequences as follows. Two sequences are first compared by the sums of their elements; when the sum of the members of two sequences are equal, the two sequences are compared by using a [[lexicographical order]] or any other [[total order]]. Since there is a finite number of sequences with a given sum, the order so defined provides a bijection between the the set of all finite sequences of natural numbers and the natural numbers. |
|||
==== Equivalence ==== |
|||
[[File:Example for a composition of two functions.svg|thumb|Example for a composition of two functions.|300x300px]] |
|||
A fundamental result necessary in developing a theory of cardinality is relating it to an [[equivalence relation]]. A binary [[Relation (mathematics)|relation]] is an equivalence relation if it satisfies the three basic properties of equality: [[Reflexive relation|reflexivity]], [[Symmetric relation|symmetry]], and [[Transitive relation|transitivity]]. |
|||
It follows that countable sets include all sets whose all elements can be unambiguously encoded with sequences of natural numbers. This includes many algebraic structures such the [[integer]]s ({{tmath|\Z}}), the [[rational number]]s ({{tmath|\Q}}), the [[polynomial]]s with rational coefficients ({{tmath|\Q[X_1, \ldots, X_n]]}}) and [[algebraic number]]s, which are all countably infinite sets. |
|||
* Reflexivity: For any set <math>A</math>, <math>A \sim A.</math><!-- |
|||
--> |
|||
** Given any set <math>A,</math> there is a bijection from <math>A</math> to itself by the [[identity function]], therefore equinumerosity is reflexive. |
|||
* Symmetry: If <math>A \sim B</math> then <math>B \sim A.</math><!-- |
|||
--> |
|||
** Given any sets <math>A</math> and <math>B,</math> such that there is a bijection <math>f</math> from <math>A</math> to <math>B,</math> then there is an [[inverse function]] <math>f^{-1}</math> from <math>B</math> to <math>A,</math> which is also bijective, therefore equinumerosity is symmetric. |
|||
* Transitivity: If <math>A \sim B</math> and <math>B \sim C</math> then <math>A \sim B.</math><!-- |
|||
--> |
|||
** Given any sets <math>A,</math> <math>B,</math> and <math>C</math> such that there is a bijection <math>f</math> from <math>A</math> to <math>B,</math> and <math>g</math> from <math>B</math> to <math>C,</math> then their [[Function composition|composition]] <math>g \circ f</math> is a bijection from <math>A</math> to <math>C,</math> and so cardinality is transitive. |
|||
The set of all [[algorithm]]s is also countably infinite, and it results that the same is true for the set of [[computable number]]s. Similarly, the set of the [[theorem]]s of a mathematical theory is also countable. |
|||
Since equinumerosity satisfies these three properties, it forms an equivalence relation. This means that cardinality, in some sense, [[Partition of a set|partitions sets]] into [[equivalence classes]], and one may assign a representative to denote this class. This motivates the notion of a [[#Cardinal numbers|cardinal number]]. Somewhat more formally, a relation must be a certain set of [[ordered pairs]]. Since there is no [[set of all sets]] in standard set theory (see: ''{{section link||Cantor's paradox}}''), equinumerosity is not a relation in the usual sense, but a [[Predicate (logic)|predicate]] or a relation over [[Class (set theory)|classes]]. |
|||
Nevertheless, there are infinite sets that are not countable; see the next section. |
|||
=== Inequality === |
|||
[[File:Cantor-Bernstein.png|thumb|256x256px|[[Gyula Kőnig]]'s definition of a bijection {{color|#00c000|''h''}}:''A'' → ''B'' from the given injections {{color|#c00000|''f''}}:''A'' → ''B'' and {{color|#0000c0|''g''}}:''B'' → ''A''. ]] |
|||
A set <math>A</math> is not larger than a set <math>B</math> if it can be mapped into <math>B</math> without overlap. That is, the cardinality of <math>A</math> is less than or equal to the cardinality of <math>B</math> if there is an [[injective function]] from <math>A</math> to '''<math>B</math>'''. This is written <math>A \preceq B,</math> <math>A \lesssim B</math> and eventually <math>|A| \leq |B|.</math> If <math>A \preceq B,</math> but there is no injection from <math>B</math> to <math>A,</math> then <math>A</math> is said to be ''strictly'' smaller than <math>B,</math> written without the underline as <math>A \prec B</math> or <math>|A| < |B|.</math> For example, if <math>A</math> has four elements and <math>B</math> has five, then the following are true <math>A \preceq A,</math> <math>A \preceq B,</math> and <math>A \prec B.</math> |
|||
== Uncountable sets == |
|||
The basic properties of an inequality are reflexivity (for any <math>a,</math> <math>a \leq a</math>), transitivity (if <math>a \leq b</math> and <math>b \leq c,</math> then <math>a \leq c</math>) and [[Antisymmetric relation|antisymmetry]] (if <math>a \leq b</math> and <math>b \leq a,</math> then <math>a = b</math>) (See [[Inequality (mathematics)#Formal definitions and generalizations|''Inequality § Formal definitions'']]). Cardinal inequality <math>(\preceq)</math> as defined above is reflexive since the [[identity function]] is injective, and is transitive by function composition. Antisymmetry is established by the [[Schröder–Bernstein theorem]]. The proof roughly goes as follows. |
|||
{{Main|Uncountable set}} |
|||
There are sets that are not countable. They are said to be ''uncountable''. That is, a ''uncountable set'' is an infinite set with a cardinality strictly larger than that of the set of the natural numbers. |
|||
===Cardinality of the continuum=== |
|||
Given sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math>, where <math>f:A \mapsto B</math> is the function that proves <math>A \preceq B</math> and <math>g: B \mapsto A</math> proves <math>B \preceq A</math>, then consider the sequence of points given by applying <math>f</math> then <math>g</math> over and over. Then we can define a bijection <math>h: A \mapsto B</math> as follows: If a sequence forms a cycle, begins with an element <math>a \in A</math> not mapped to by <math>g</math>, or extends infinitley in both directions, define <math>h(x) = f(x)</math> for each <math>x \in A</math> in those sequences. The last case, if a sequence begins with an element <math>b \in B</math>, not mapped to by <math>f</math>, define <math>h(x) = g^{-1}(x)</math> for each <math>x \in A</math> in that sequence. Then <math>h</math> is a bijection. |
|||
{{main|Cardinality of the continuum}} |
|||
The first prof of the existence of uncountable sets was given by [[Georg Cantor]] in 1891, who proved that the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] {{tmath|(0,1)}} of the [[real line]] is uncountable.<ref name="Cantor.1891">{{cite journal |author=Georg Cantor |year=1891 |title=Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre |url=https://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PID=GDZPPN002113910&physid=phys84#navi |journal=[[Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung]] |volume=1 |pages=75–78}} English translation: {{cite book |title=From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, Volume 2 |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1996 |isbn=0-19-850536-1 |editor-last=Ewald |editor-first=William B. |pages=920–922}}</ref> |
|||
In a second proof, he used what is now called [[Cantor's diagonal argument]] to prove that a function from the natural numbers to the interval {{tmath|1=I=(0,1)}} cannot be surjective, and is therefore not a bijection. Indeed, if {{tmath|f:\N \to I}} is such a function, one can define a number of the interval that is not of the form {{tmath|f(n)}}. Such a number is obtained with a number {{tmath|X}} such that, for every {{tmath|k}}, the {{tmath|k}}th decimal digit of {{tmath|X}} differs from the {{tmath|k}}th digit of {{tmath|f(k)}} and differs also from {{tmath|0}} anf {{tmath|1}} (the latter condition for avoiding numbers that have two decimal representations). The term "diagonal argument" refers to the fact that, one can write an (infinite) [[matrix (mathematics)|matrix]] such the {{tmath|(i,j)}} entry is the {{tmath|j}}th digit of {{tmath|f(i)}}, and, then, the digits of {{tmath|X}} are obtained by changing the digits of the diagonal of the matrix.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Bloch |first=Ethan D. |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-1-4419-7127-2 |title=Proofs and Fundamentals |date=2011 |publisher=Springer Science+Business Media |series=Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics |pages=242–243 |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-1-4419-7127-2 |isbn=978-1-4419-7126-5 |issn=0172-6056 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/proofsfundamenta0002bloc/ |archive-date=2022-01-22}}</ref> Then, this number {{tmath|X}} will be different from each of the numbers in the list by at least one digit, and therefore must not be in the list. This shows that the real numbers cannot be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the naturals, and thus must be strictly larger.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Ashlock |first1=Daniel |last2=Lee |first2=Colin |date=2020 |title=An Introduction to Proofs with Set Theory |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-031-02426-9 |publisher=Springer Cham |series=Synthesis Lectures on Mathematics & Statistics |language=en |pages=181–182 |doi=10.1007/978-3-031-02426-9 |isbn=978-3-031-01298-3 |issn=1938-1743}}</ref> |
|||
The above shows that cardinal inequality is a [[partial order]]. A [[total order]] has the additional property that, for any <math>a</math> and <math>b</math>, either <math>a \leq b</math> or <math>b \leq a.</math> This can be established by the [[well-ordering theorem]]. Every well-ordered set is [[order isomorphic|isomorphic]] to a unique [[ordinal number]], called the [[order type]] of the set. Then, by comparing their order types, one can show that <math>A \preceq B</math> or <math>B \preceq A</math>. This result is equivalent to the [[axiom of choice]].<ref>{{citation | author=Friedrich M. Hartogs | author-link=Friedrich M. Hartogs | editor=Felix Klein | editor-link=Felix Klein |editor2=Walther von Dyck |editor2-link=Walther von Dyck |editor3=David Hilbert |editor3-link=David Hilbert |editor4=Otto Blumenthal |editor4-link=Otto Blumenthal | title=Über das Problem der Wohlordnung | journal=[[Mathematische Annalen]] | volume=76 | number=4 | publisher=B. G. Teubner | location=Leipzig | year=1915 | pages=438–443 | issn=0025-5831 |url=http://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/index.php?id=11&PPN=PPN235181684_0076&DMDID=DMDLOG_0037&L=1 | doi=10.1007/bf01458215| s2cid=121598654 }}</ref><ref>{{citation | author=Felix Hausdorff | author-link=Felix Hausdorff | editor=Egbert Brieskorn | editor-link=Egbert Brieskorn |editor2=Srishti D. Chatterji| title=Grundzüge der Mengenlehre | edition=1. | publisher=Springer | location=Berlin/Heidelberg | year=2002 | pages=587 | isbn=3-540-42224-2| url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3nth_p-6DpcC|display-editors=etal}} - [https://jscholarship.library.jhu.edu/handle/1774.2/34091 Original edition (1914)]</ref> |
|||
One has |
|||
=== Countable sets === |
|||
<math display =block>\operatorname{card}(\R)=\operatorname{card}(I),</math> |
|||
{{Main|Countable set}} |
|||
since the function {{tmath|x\mapsto \tan(x\pi-\pi/2)}} is a bijection between these two sets. |
|||
A set is called ''[[countable]]'' if it is [[Finite set|finite]] or has a bijection with the set of [[natural number]]s <math>(\N),</math> in which case it is called ''countably infinite''. The term ''[[denumerable]]'' is also sometimes used for countably infinite sets. For example, the set of all even natural numbers is countable, and therefore has the same cardinality as the whole set of natural numbers, even though it is a [[proper subset]]. Similarly, the set of [[square numbers]] is countable, which was considered paradoxical for hundreds of years before modern set theory (see: ''{{section link||Pre-Cantorian set theory}}''). However, several other examples have historically been considered surprising or initially unintuitive since the rise of set theory. |
|||
This cardinality is called the ''cardinality of the continuum'' and commonly denoted as {{tmath|\mathfrak c}} ("the continuum" is a old name for the real line). |
|||
{{Multiple image |
|||
| direction = horizontal |
|||
[[Space-filling curve]]s show that every finite dimensional [[real vector space]] has the cardinality of the continuum, as well as almost all [[space (mathematics)|spaces]] considered in [[geometry]] and [[analysis (mathematics)|analysis]]. So, almost all uncountable sets that are encountered in mathematics have the cardinality of the continuum. |
|||
| image1 = Diagonal argument.svg |
|||
| image2 = Straight counter-clockwise spiral path in square grid.png |
|||
=== Powersets === |
|||
| total_width = 330 |
|||
| footer = Two images of a visual depiction of a function from <math>\N</math> to <math>\Q.</math> On the left, a version for the positive rational numbers. On the right, a spiral for all pairs of integers <math>(p,q)</math> for each fraction <math>p/q.</math> |
|||
There are many other cardinalities than those described above. The most common method for defining sets with larger cardinalities is with [[powerset]]s. |
|||
}} |
|||
The ''powerset'' <math>\mathcal{P}(S)</math> of a set {{tmath|S}} is the set of all subsets of {{tmath|S}}. It often identified with the set of all functions of {{tmath|S}} to {{tmath|\{0,1\} }}, through the one-to-one correspondence associating to such a function the subset where it takes the value {{tmath|1}}. |
|||
[[File:Diagonal argument powerset svg.svg|thumb|255x255px|Proof with the diagonal argument that <math>\operatorname{card}(\mathcal P(\N) >\operatorname{card}(\N)\colon</math> The set <math>T = \{n \in N : n \notin f(n) \}</math> formed by removing the red digits cannot occur an any row.]] |
|||
The cardinality of <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math> is the cardinality of the continuum. This can be proven by considering the sequence of the digits of the [[binary representation]] of a real number in the interval {{tmath|(0,1)}} as a function from {{tmath|\N}} to {{tmath|\{0,1\} }}. |
|||
More generally, [[Cantor's theorem]] asserts that for every set {{tmath|S}}, one has |
|||
<math display=block>\operatorname{card}(\mathcal P(S))> \operatorname{card}(S).</math> |
|||
This can be proved with a variant of Cantor's diagonal agument: one has <math display=inline>\operatorname{card}(\mathcal P(S))\ge \operatorname{card}(S),</math> since the map {{tmath|x\mapsto \{x\} }} is an injective function from {{tmath|S}} to {{tmath|\mathcal P(S)}}. So, it suffices to prove that there is no bijection between {{tmath|S}} and {{tmath|\mathcal P(S)}}, and, in particular, that a function from {{tmath|S}} to {{tmath|\mathcal P(S)}} cannot be surjective. |
|||
So, let {{tmath|f}} be a function from {{tmath|S}} to {{tmath|\mathcal P(S)}}. The subset <math>T = \{x \in S : x \notin f(x) \}\in \mathcal P(S)</math> cannot be in the [[image of a function|image]] of {{tmath|f}}, since if one would have <math>T=f(x)</math> then either <math>x\in f(x)</math> or <math>x\in f(x),</math> but not both. The definition of {{tmath|T}} implies that if one is in any of the two cases, one is also in the other case, a contradiction that proves that {{tmath|f}} is not surjective. |
|||
The [[rational numbers]] <math>(\Q)</math> are those which can be expressed as the [[quotient]] or [[Fraction (mathematics)|fraction]] {{tmath|\tfrac p q}} of two [[integer]]s. The rational numbers can be shown to be countable by considering the set of fractions as the set of all [[ordered pairs]] of integers, denoted <math>\Z\times\Z,</math> which can be visualized as the set of all [[Integer lattice|integer points]] on a grid. Then, an intuitive function can be described by drawing a line in a repeating pattern, or spiral, which eventually goes through each point in the grid. For example, going through each diagonal on the grid for positive fractions, or through a lattice spiral for all integer pairs. These technically over cover the rationals, since, for example, the rational number <math display="inline">\frac{1}{2}</math> gets mapped to by all the fractions <math display="inline">\frac{2}{4},\, \frac{3}{6}, \, \frac{4}{8}, \, \dots ,</math> as the grid method treats these all as distinct ordered pairs. So this function shows <math>|\Q| \leq |\N|</math> not <math>|\Q| = |\N|.</math> This can be corrected by "skipping over" these numbers in the grid, or by designing a function which does this naturally, for example using the [[Calkin–Wilf tree]]. |
|||
[[File:Algebraicszoom.png|thumb|273x273px|Algebraic numbers on the [[complex plane]], colored by degree]] |
|||
A number is called [[Algebraic number|algebraic]] if it is a solution of some [[polynomial]] equation (with integer [[coefficient]]s). For example, the [[square root of two]] <math>\sqrt2</math> is a solution to <math>x^2 - 2 = 0,</math> and the rational number <math>p/q</math> is the solution to <math>qx - p = 0.</math> Conversely, a number which cannot be the root of any polynomial is called [[Transcendental number|transcendental]]. Two examples include [[Euler's number]] (''{{mvar|e}}'') and [[Pi|pi ({{pi}})]]. In general, proving a number is transcendental is considered to be very difficult, and only a few classes of transcendental numbers are known. However, it can be shown that the set of algebraic numbers is countable (for example, see ''{{slink|Cantor's first set theory article|The proofs}}''). Since the set of algebraic numbers is countable while the real numbers are uncountable (shown in the following section), the transcendental numbers must form the vast majority of real numbers, even though they are individually much harder to identify. That is to say, [[almost all]] real numbers are transcendental. |
|||
A [[transfinite induction]] using powerset construction and starting from the natural numbers allows giving values, called [[beth number]]s, to some cardinalities. These beth numbers are uniquely defined sets defined by: |
|||
=== Uncountable sets === |
|||
*<math>\beth_0=\N</math> |
|||
{{hatnote group|{{Main|Uncountable set}}{{Further information|#Cardinality of the continuum}}}}A set is called ''[[uncountable]]'' if it is not countable. That is, it is infinite and strictly larger than the set of natural numbers. The usual first example of this is the set of [[real numbers]] <math>(\R)</math>, which can be understood as the set of all numbers on the [[number line]]. One method of proving that the reals are uncountable is called [[Cantor's diagonal argument]], credited to Cantor for his 1891 proof,<ref name="Cantor.1891">{{cite journal |author=Georg Cantor |year=1891 |title=Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre |url=https://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PID=GDZPPN002113910&physid=phys84#navi |journal=[[Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung]] |volume=1 |pages=75–78}} English translation: {{cite book |title=From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, Volume 2 |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1996 |isbn=0-19-850536-1 |editor-last=Ewald |editor-first=William B. |pages=920–922}}</ref> though his differs from the more common presentation. |
|||
*<math>\beth_1=\mathcal P(\N)=\mathfrak c</math> |
|||
*<math>\beth_{\alpha+1}=\mathcal P(\beth_\alpha)\quad</math> for every [[ordinal number|ordinal]] <math>\alpha</math> |
|||
*<math>\beth_\lambda=\bigcup_{\alpha<\lambda}\beth_\alpha\quad</math> for every [[limit ordinal]] <math>\lambda</math> |
|||
Unless if the [[generalized continuum hypothesis]] is assumed, not all cardinalities can be represented by beth numbers. |
|||
It begins by assuming, [[Proof by contradiction|by contradiction]], that there is some one-to-one mapping between the natural numbers and the set of real numbers between 0 and 1 (the interval <math>[0,1]</math>). Then, take the [[decimal expansion]]s of each real number, which looks like <math>0.d_1d_2d_3...</math> Considering these real numbers in a column, create a new number such that the first digit of the new number is different from that of the first number in the column, the second digit is different from the second number in the column and so on. We also need to make sure that the number we create has a unique decimal representation, that is, it cannot end in [[0.999...|repeating nines]] or repeating zeros. For example, if the digit isn't a 7, make the digit of the new number a 7, and if it was a seven, make it a 3.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Bloch |first=Ethan D. |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-1-4419-7127-2 |title=Proofs and Fundamentals |date=2011 |publisher=Springer Science+Business Media |series=Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics |pages=242–243 |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-1-4419-7127-2 |isbn=978-1-4419-7126-5 |issn=0172-6056 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/proofsfundamenta0002bloc/ |archive-date=2022-01-22}}</ref> Then, this new number will be different from each of the numbers in the list by at least one digit, and therefore must not be in the list. This shows that the real numbers cannot be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the naturals, and thus must be strictly larger.<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Ashlock |first1=Daniel |last2=Lee |first2=Colin |date=2020 |title=An Introduction to Proofs with Set Theory |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-031-02426-9 |publisher=Springer Cham |series=Synthesis Lectures on Mathematics & Statistics |language=en |pages=181–182 |doi=10.1007/978-3-031-02426-9 |isbn=978-3-031-01298-3 |issn=1938-1743}}</ref> |
|||
===Continuum hypothesis === |
|||
[[File:Diagonal argument powerset svg.svg|thumb|255x255px|<math>\N</math> does not have the same cardinality as its [[power set]] <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math>: For every function ''f'' from '''<math>\N</math>''' to <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math>, the set <math>T = \{n \in N : n \notin f(n) \}</math> disagrees with every set in the [[range of a function|range]] of <math>f</math>, hence <math>f</math> cannot be surjective. The picture shows an example <math>f</math> and the corresponding <math>T</math>; {{color|#800000|'''red'''}}: <math>n \notin T</math>, {{color|#000080|'''blue'''}}: <math>n \in T</math>.]]Another classical example of an uncountable set, established using a related reasoning, is the [[power set]] of the natural numbers, denoted <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math>. This is the set of all [[subsets]] of <math>\N</math>, including the [[empty set]] and <math>\N</math> itself. The method is much closer to Cantor's original diagonal argument. Again, assume by contradiction that there exists a one-to-one correspondence <math>f</math> between <math>\N</math> and <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math>, so that every subset of <math>\N</math> is assigned to some natural number. These subsets are then placed in a column, in the order defined by <math>f</math> (see image). Now, one may define a subset <math>T</math> of <math>\N</math> which is not in the list by taking the negation of the "diagonal" of this column as follows: |
|||
{{main article|Continuum hypothesis}} |
|||
The continuum hypothesis is the assertion that there is no set {{tmath|S}} such that {{tmath|\operatorname{card}(\N)< \operatorname{card}(S) < \operatorname{card}(\R)}}. With the axiom of choice, the continuum hypothesis implies that the cardinal of the continuum is the least uncountable cardinal. |
|||
If <math>1 \in f(1)</math>, then <math>1 \notin T</math>, that is, if 1 is in the first subset of the list, then 1 is ''not'' in the subset <math>T</math>. Further, if <math>2 \notin f(2) </math>, then <math>2 \in T</math>, that is if the number 2 is not in the second subset of the column, then 2 ''is'' in the subset <math>T</math>. Then in general, for each natural number <math>n</math>, <math>n \in T</math> if and only if <math>n \notin f(n) </math>, meaning <math>n</math> is put in the subset <math>T</math> only if the nth subset in the column does not contain the number <math>n</math>. Then, for each natural number <math>n</math>, <math>T \neq f(n)</math>, meaning, <math>T</math> is not the nth subset in the list, for any number <math>n</math>, and so it cannot appear anywhere in the list defined by <math>f</math>. Since <math>f</math> was chosen arbitrarily, this shows that every function from <math>\N</math> to <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math> must be missing at least one element, therefore no such bijection can exist, and so <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math> must be not be countable. |
|||
The proof of the continuum hypothesis was the first of the [[Hilbert's problems]], stated in 1900. |
|||
These two sets, <math>\R</math> and <math>\mathcal{P}(\N)</math> can be shown to have the same cardinality (by, for example, assigning each subset to a decimal expansion). Whether there exists a set <math>A</math> with cardinality between these two sets <math>|\N| < |A| < |\R|</math> is known as the [[continuum hypothesis]]. |
|||
In the framework of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] (ZF), [[Paul Cohen]] proved in 1963, that the continuum hypothesis is independent from the other axioms of set theory, with or without the [[axiom of choice]]. More precicely, if ZF is consistent (that is, not self contradictory), then both ZF with ths continuum hypothesis and ZF with the negation of the continuum hypothesis are consistent, and they remain consistent if either the axiom of choice or its negation are added to the theory.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=Paul J. |date=December 15, 1963 |title=The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=50 |issue=6 |pages=1143–1148 |bibcode=1963PNAS...50.1143C |doi=10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 |jstor=71858 |pmc=221287 |pmid=16578557 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=Paul J. |date=January 15, 1964 |title=The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=51 |issue=1 |pages=105–110 |bibcode=1964PNAS...51..105C |doi=10.1073/pnas.51.1.105 |jstor=72252 |pmc=300611 |pmid=16591132 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Penrose |first=R |title=The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe |year=2005 |publisher=Vintage Books |isbn=0-09-944068-7 |author-link=Roger Penrose}}</ref> |
|||
[[Cantor's theorem]] generalizes the second theorem above, showing that every set is strictly smaller than its powerset. The proof roughly goes as follows: Given a set <math>A</math>, assume by contradiction that there is a bijection <math>f</math> from <math>A</math> to <math>\mathcal{P}(A)</math>. Then, the subset <math>T \subseteq A</math> given by taking the negation of the "diagonal", formally, <math>T = \{ a \in A : a \notin f(a) \}</math>, cannot be in the list. Therefore, every function is missing at least one element, and so <math>|A| < |\mathcal{P}(A)|</math>. Further, since <math>\mathcal{P}(A)</math> is itself a set, the argument can be repeated to show <math>|A| < |\mathcal{P}(A)| < |\mathcal{P}(\mathcal{P}(A))|</math>. Taking <math>A = \N</math>, this shows that <math>\mathcal{P}(\mathcal{P}(\N))</math> is even larger than <math>\mathcal{P}(\N) </math>, which was already shown to be uncountable. Repeating this argument shows that there are infinitely many "sizes" of infinity. |
|||
==Cardinal numbers== |
==Cardinal numbers== |
||
{{main|Cardinal number|Aleph number}} |
|||
{{main|Cardinal number}}In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined relationally. In other words, while it was closely tied to the concept of number, the meaning of "number of elements" has not yet been defined. This can be formalized from basic set-theoretic principles, relying on some number-like structures. For finite sets, this is simply the [[natural number]] found by counting the elements. This number is called the ''cardinal number'' of that set, or simply ''the cardinality'' of that set. The cardinal number of a set <math>A</math> is generally denoted by <math>|A|,</math> with a [[vertical bar]] on each side,<ref name=":7">{{Cite web |title=Cardinality {{!}} Brilliant Math & Science Wiki |url=https://brilliant.org/wiki/cardinality/ |access-date=2020-08-23 |website=brilliant.org |language=en-us}}</ref> though it may also be denoted by <math>n(A),</math> <span style="border-top: 3px double;"><math>A</math></span>, <math>\operatorname{card}(A),</math> or <math>\#A.</math> |
|||
In the preceding sections, the "cardinality" of a set was defined relationally. That is, the cardinalities of two sets can be compared, but the cardinality of a specific set was not defined as a [[mathematical object]]. |
|||
The first tentatives for defining cardinalities were to define them as [[equivalence class]]es for the relation "having the same cardinality". Unfortunately, this does not work beause these equivalence classes are not sets. So, the approach that has been eventually chosen is to define once for all specific sets, called ''cardinal numbers'' or ''aleph numbers'', such that every set is equinumerous with exactly one cardinal number. |
|||
For infinite sets, "cardinal number" is somewhat more difficult to define formally. However, cardinal numbers are not usually thought of in terms of their formal definition, but immaterially in terms of their arithmetic/algebraic properties. For example, defining <math>|\N| = \aleph_0</math>, and <math>A \sim B</math> if and only if <math>|A| = |B| </math>. Then <math>2^{\aleph_0} = |\mathcal{P}(\N)| \sim |\R|. </math> |
|||
The definition of cardinal numbers involves a [[transfinite induction]] and uses [[ordinal number]]s, which are [[well ordered set]]s such that every well-ordered set is [[order isomorphic]] to exactly one ordinal number. |
|||
=== Finite sets === |
|||
{{main|Finite set}} |
|||
[[File:Bijection.svg|thumb|200x200px|A [[bijective function]], ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'', from set ''X'' to set ''Y'' demonstrates that the sets have the same cardinality, in this case equal to the cardinal number 4.]]Given a basic sense of [[natural numbers]], a set is said to have cardinality <math>n</math> if it can be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> For example, the set <math>S = \{ A,B,C,D \} </math> has a natural correspondence with the set <math>\{1,2,3,4\},</math> and therefore is said to have cardinality 4. Other terminologies include "Its cardinality is 4" or "Its cardinal number is 4". While this definition uses a basic sense of natural numbers, it may be that cardinality is used to define the natural numbers, in which case, a simple construction of objects satisfying the [[Peano axioms]] can be used as a substitute. Most commonly, the [[Von Neumann ordinal]]s. |
|||
The [[axiom of choice]] states that every set can be well ordered. This implies that, without the axiom of choice, there may be cardinalities that do not correspond to a cardinal number. |
|||
Showing that such a correspondence exists is not always trivial, which is the subject matter of [[combinatorics]]. |
|||
Formally, the infinite cardinal mumbers, also called aleph numbers because they are denoted with the [[Hebrew alphabet|Hebrew letter]] ''aleph'', are defined as follows: |
|||
==== Uniqueness ==== |
|||
* <math>\aleph_0=\N\quad</math> (<math>\N</math> is the least infinite ordinal) |
|||
An intuitive property of finite sets is that, for example, if a set has cardinality 4, then it cannot also have cardinality 5. Intuitively meaning that a set cannot have both exactly 4 elements and exactly 5 elements. However, it is not so obviously proven. The following proof is adapted from ''Analysis I'' by [[Terence Tao]].{{Sfn|Tao|2022|p=59}} |
|||
* For every ordinal <math>\alpha,</math> one defines <math>\aleph_{\alpha + 1}</math> as the least ordinal <math>\beta</math> such that <math>\operatorname{card}(\beta)> \operatorname{card}(\aleph_\alpha)</math> |
|||
* For every limit ordinal <math>\lambda,</math> one define <math>\aleph_{\lambda}</math> as the least ordinal <math>\mu</math> such that <math>\operatorname{card}(\mu)> \operatorname{card}(\aleph_\alpha)</math> for all <math>\alpha<\lambda</math> |
|||
If one starts the transfinite induction with the empty set {{tmath|\emptyset}} instead of {{tmath|\N}}, the first cardinal numbers become the |
|||
Lemma: If a set <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n \geq 1,</math> and <math>x_0 \in X,</math> then the set <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> (i.e. <math>X</math> with the element <math>x_0</math> removed) has cardinality <math>n-1.</math> |
|||
[[von Neumann natural number]]s. |
|||
==History== |
|||
Proof: Given <math>X</math> as above, since <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n,</math> there is a bijection <math>f</math> from <math>X</math> to <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> Then, since <math>x_0 \in X,</math> there must be some number <math>f(x_0)</math> in <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> We need to find a bijection from <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> to <math>\{1, \dots n-1\}</math> (which may be empty). Define a function <math>g</math> such that <math>g(x) = f(x)</math> for all <math>x \neq n</math> and <math>g(n) = f(x_0) </math>. Then <math>g</math> is a bijection from <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> to <math>\{1, \dots n-1\}.</math> |
|||
=== Etymology === |
|||
Theorem: If a set <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n,</math> then it cannot have any other cardinality. That is, <math>X</math> cannot also have cardinality <math>m \neq n.</math> |
|||
In English, the term ''cardinality'' originates from the [[Post-Classical Latin language|post-classical Latin]] ''cardinalis'', meaning "principal" or "chief", which derives from ''cardo'', a noun meaning "hinge". In Latin, ''cardo'' referred to something central or pivotal, both literally and metaphorically. This concept of centrality passed into [[medieval Latin]] and then into English, where ''cardinal'' came to describe things considered to be, in some sense, fundamental, such as ''[[cardinal virtues]]'', ''[[cardinal sins]]'', ''[[cardinal directions]]'', and (in the grammatical sense) ''[[Cardinal numbers (linguistics)|cardinal numbers]].<ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "cardinal (adj.), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/1490074521.</ref>''<ref>Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinal," [[Etymonline]], Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinal.</ref> The last of which referred to numbers used for counting (e.g., one, two, three),<ref>''[[Oxford English Dictionary]]'', "cardinal number (''n.''), sense 1," July 2023, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/3193437451.</ref> as opposed to ''[[Ordinal numbers (linguistics)|ordinal numbers]]'', which express order (e.g., first, second, third),<ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "ordinal (n.2)," June 2024, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/6032173309.</ref> and [[Nominal number|''nominal numbers'']] used for labeling without meaning (e.g., [[jersey numbers]] and [[serial numbers]]).<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Woodin |first1=Greg |last2=Winter |first2=Bodo |year=2024 |title=Numbers in Context: Cardinals, Ordinals, and Nominals in American English |journal=Cognitive Science |volume=48 |doi=10.1111/cogs.13471 |pmc=11475258 |pmid=38895756 |doi-access=free |article-number=e13471 |number=6}}</ref> |
|||
In mathematics, the notion of cardinality was first introduced by [[Georg Cantor]] in the late 19th century, wherein he used the used the term ''Mächtigkeit'', which may be translated as "magnitude" or "power", though Cantor credited the term to a work by [[Jakob Steiner]] on [[projective geometry]].<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Ferreirós |first=José |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3 |title=Labyrinth of Thought |date=2007 |publisher=[[Birkhäuser]] |isbn=978-3-7643-8349-7 |edition=2nd |location=Basel |pages=24 |doi=10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3}}</ref><ref name=":3">{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |author-link=Georg Cantor |date=1932 |editor-last=Zermelo |editor-first=Ernst |editor-link=Ernst Zermelo |title=Gesammelte Abhandlungen |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2 |journal=Springer |location=Berlin |pages=151 |doi=10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2 |isbn=978-3-662-00254-4}}</ref><ref name=":4">{{Cite book |last=Steiner |first=Jacob |url=https://archive.org/details/bub_gb_jCgPAAAAQAAJ/ |title=Vorlesungen über synthetische Geometrie / 1 Die Theorie der Kegelschnitte in elementarer Form |date=1867 |publisher=Leipzig : Teubner |others=Ghent University}}</ref> The terms ''cardinality'' and ''cardinal number'' were eventually adopted from the grammatical sense, and later translations would use these terms.<ref>Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinality," [[Etymonline]], Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinality.</ref><ref>[[Oxford English Dictionary]], "cardinality (n.2), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/5444748676.</ref> |
|||
Proof: If <math>X</math> is empty (has cardinality 0), then there cannot exist a bijection from <math>X</math> to any nonempty set <math>Y,</math> since nothing mapped to <math>y_0 \in Y.</math> Assume, by [[Mathematical induction|induction]] that the result has been proven up to some cardinality <math>n.</math> If <math>X,</math> has cardinality <math>n+1,</math> assume it also has cardinality <math>m.</math> We want to show that <math>m = n+1.</math> By the lemma above, <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> must have cardinality <math>n</math> and <math>m-1.</math> Since, by induction, cardinality is unique for sets with cardinality <math>n,</math> it must be that <math>m-1 = n,</math> and thus <math>m = n+1.</math> |
|||
=== Prehistory === |
|||
{{Further|Tally marks#Early history| History of ancient numeral systems}} |
|||
{{Main|Combinatorial principles}} |
|||
[[File:Inclusion-exclusion.svg|thumb|[[Inclusion–exclusion]] illustrated for three sets.]] |
|||
[[Combinatorics]] is the area of mathematics primarily concerned with [[counting]], both as a means and as an end to obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. The notion cardinality of finite sets is closely tied to many basic [[combinatorial principles]], and provides a set-theoretic foundation to prove them. The above shows uniqueness of finite cardinal numbers, and therefore, <math>A \sim B</math> if and only if <math>|A| = |B|</math>, formalizing the notion of a [[bijective proof]]. |
|||
A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.<ref>Cepelewicz, Jordana ''[https://www.quantamagazine.org/animals-can-count-and-use-zero-how-far-does-their-number-sense-go-20210809/ Animals Count and Use Zero. How Far Does Their Number Sense Go?]'', [[Quanta Magazine|Quanta]], August 9, 2021</ref> Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as {{val|40,000}} years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://mathtimeline.weebly.com/early-human-counting-tools.html|title=Early Human Counting Tools|website=Math Timeline|access-date=2018-04-26}}</ref> The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian [[History of mathematics|mathematics]] and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.<ref>Duncan J. Melville (2003). [http://it.stlawu.edu/~dmelvill/mesomath/3Mill/chronology.html Third Millennium Chronology] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180707213616/http://it.stlawu.edu/~dmelvill/mesomath/3Mill/chronology.html |date=2018-07-07 }}, ''Third Millennium Mathematics''. [[St. Lawrence University]].</ref> |
|||
The [[addition principle]] asserts that given [[Disjoint sets|disjoint]] sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math>, <math>|A \cup B| = |A| + |B|</math>, intuitively meaning that the sum of parts is equal to the sum of the whole. The [[multiplication principle]] asserts that given two sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math>, <math>|A \times B| = |A| \cdot |B|</math>, intuitively meaning that there are <math>|A| \cdot |B|</math> ways to pair objects from these sets. Both of these can be proven by a bijective proof, together with induction. The more general result is the [[inclusion–exclusion principle]], which defines how to count the number of elements in overlapping sets. |
|||
=== |
=== Ancient history === |
||
[[File:AristotlesWheelLabeledDiagram.svg|thumb|252x252px|Diagram of Aristotle's wheel as described in ''Mechanica''.]] |
|||
{{Main|Aleph number}} |
|||
From the 6th century BCE, the writings of [[Greek philosophers]], such as [[Anaximander]], show hints of comparing infinite sets or shapes. While the Greeks considered notions of infinity, they viewed it as paradoxical and imperfect (cf. ''[[Zeno's paradoxes]]''), often associating good and evil with finite and infinite.<ref name="Allen22">{{Cite web |last=Allen |first=Donald |date=2003 |title=The History of Infinity |url=https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200801202539/https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |archive-date=August 1, 2020 |access-date=Nov 15, 2019 |website=Texas A&M Mathematics}}</ref> [[Aristotle]] distinguished between the notions of [[actual infinity]] and potential infinity, arguing that Greek mathematicians understood the difference, and that they "do not need the [actual] infinite and do not use it."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Allen |first1=Reginald E. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3bNw_OmGNwYC&pg=PA256 |title=Plato's Parmenides |publisher=Yale University Press |year=1998 |isbn=9780300138030 |series=The Dialogues of Plato |volume=4 |location=New Haven |page=256 |oclc=47008500}}</ref> The greek notion of number (''αριθμός'', ''arithmos'') was used exclusively for a definite number of definite objects (i.e. finite numbers).<ref>{{Cite book |last=Klein |first=Jacob |author-link=Jacob Klein (philosopher) |url=http://archive.org/details/jacob-klein-greek-mathematical-thought-and-the-origin-of-algebra |title=Greek Mathematical Thought And The Origin Of Algebra |date=1992 |publisher=[[Dover Publications]] |isbn=0-486-27289-3 |location=New York |page=46 |translator-last=Brann |translator-first=Eva |lccn=92-20992 |orig-year=1934 |translator-link=Eva Brann}}</ref> This would be codified in [[Euclid's Elements|Euclid's ''Elements'']], where the [[Euclidean geometry#common notions|fifth common notion]] states "The whole is greater than the part", often called the ''Euclidean principle''. This principle would be the dominating philosophy in mathematics until the 19th century.<ref name="Allen22" /><ref>{{Cite book |last=Mayberry |first=John P. |url=http://archive.org/details/foundationsofmat0000john |title=Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets |date=2011 |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |isbn=978-0-521-17271-4 |series=Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications |issn=0953-4806}}</ref> |
|||
[[File:Aleph0.svg|right|thumb|169x169px|[[Aleph-nought]], aleph-zero, or aleph-null: the smallest infinite cardinal number, and the cardinal number of the set of natural numbers. ]] |
|||
The [[aleph numbers]] are a sequence of cardinal numbers that denote the size of [[infinite sets]], denoted with an [[aleph]] <math>\aleph,</math> the first letter of the [[Hebrew alphabet]]. The first aleph number is <math>\aleph_0,</math> called "aleph-nought", "aleph-zero", or "aleph-null", which represents the cardinality of the set of all [[natural numbers]]: <math>\aleph_0 = |\N| = |\{0,1,2,3,\cdots\}| .</math> Then, <math>\aleph_1</math> represents the next largest cardinality. The most common way this is formalized in set theory is through [[Von Neumann ordinal]]s, known as [[Von Neumann cardinal assignment]]. |
|||
Around the 4th century BCE, [[Jaina mathematics]] would be the first to discuss different sizes of infinity. They defined three major classes of number: enumerable (finite numbers), unenumerable (''asamkhyata'', roughly, [[#Countable sets|countably infinite]]), and infinite (''ananta''). Then they had five classes of infinite numbers: infinite in one direction, infinite in both directions, infinite in area, infinite everywhere, and infinite perpetually.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Joseph |first=George Gheverghese |author-link=George Gheverghese Joseph |url=https://press.princeton.edu/books/paperback/9780691135267/the-crest-of-the-peacock |title=The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics |date=Oct 24, 2010 |publisher=[[Princeton University Press]] |isbn=978-0-691-13526-7 |edition=3rd |location=Princeton, New Jersey |pages=349-351 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/crest-of-the-peacock-joseph-george-gheverghese |archive-date=2024-08-05}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |last=O'Connor |first=John J. |last2=Robertson |first2=Edmund F. |author-link2=E. F. Robertson |date=2000 |title=MacTutor{{snd}}Jaina mathematics |url=https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/HistTopics/Jaina_mathematics/ |access-date=2025-06-09 |website=[[MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive]] |language=en |via=[[University of St Andrews]], Scotland}}</ref> |
|||
[[Ordinal number]]s generalize the notion of ''order'' to infinite sets. For example, 2 comes after 1, denoted <math>1 < 2,</math> and 3 comes after both, denoted <math>1 < 2 < 3.</math> Then, one defines a new number, <math>\omega,</math> which comes after every natural number, denoted <math>1 < 2 < 3 < \cdots < \omega.</math> Further <math>\omega < \omega+1 ,</math> and so on. More formally, these ordinal numbers can be defined as follows: |
|||
One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded in [[Mechanics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's ''Mechanics'']] ({{Circa|350 BCE}}), known as [[Aristotle's wheel paradox]]. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as two [[concentric circles]]. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: the [[circumference]] of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Drabkin |first=Israel E. |date=1950 |title=Aristotle's Wheel: Notes on the History of a Paradox |journal=Osiris |volume=9 |pages=162–198 |doi=10.1086/368528 |jstor=301848 |s2cid=144387607}}</ref> Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.<ref name="Allen22" /> |
|||
<math>0 := \{\},</math> the [[empty set]], <math>1 := \{0\} ,</math> <math>2 := \{0,1\},</math> <math>3 := \{0,1,2\},</math> and so on. Then one can define <math>m < n \text{, if } \, m \in n,</math> for examlpe, <math>2 \in \{0,1,2\} = 3,</math> therefore <math>2 < 3.</math> Defining <math>\omega := \{0,1,2,3,\cdots\}</math> (a [[limit ordinal]]) gives <math>\omega</math> the desired property of being the smallest ordinal greater than all finite ordinal numbers. Further, <math>\omega+1 := \{1,2,\cdots,\omega\}</math>, and so on. |
|||
=== Pre-Cantorian set theory === |
|||
Since <math>\omega \sim \N</math> by the natural correspondence, one may define <math>\aleph_0</math> as the set of all finite ordinals. That is, <math>\aleph_0 := \omega.</math> Then, <math>\aleph_1</math> is the set of all countable ordinals (all ordinals <math>\kappa</math> with cardinality <math>|\kappa| \leq \aleph_0</math>), the [[first uncountable ordinal]]. Since a set cannot contain itself, <math>\aleph_1</math> must have a strictly larger cardinality: <math>\aleph_0 < \aleph_1.</math> Furthermore, <math>\aleph_2</math> is the set of all ordinals with cardinality <math>\aleph_1,</math> and so on. By the [[well-ordering theorem]], there cannot exist any set with cardinality between <math>\aleph_0</math> and <math>\aleph_1,</math> and every infinite set has some cardinality corresponding to some aleph <math>\aleph_\alpha,</math> for some ordinal <math>\alpha.</math> |
|||
{{Multiple image |
|||
| direction = horizontal |
|||
| image1 = Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) RMG BHC2700.tiff |
|||
| image2 = Bernard Bolzano.jpg |
|||
| total_width = 350 |
|||
| footer = Portrait of [[Galileo Galilei]], circa 1640 (left). Portrait of [[Bernard Bolzano]] 1781–1848 (right). |
|||
}} |
|||
[[Galileo Galilei]] presented what was later coined [[Galileo's paradox]] in his book ''[[Two New Sciences]]'' (1638), where he attempts to show that infinite quantities cannot be called greater or less than one another. He presents the paradox roughly as follows: a [[square number]] is one which is the product of another number with itself, such as 4 and 9, which are the squares of 2 and 3, respectively. Then the [[square root]] of a square number is that multiplicand. He then notes that there are as many square numbers as there are square roots, since every square has its own root and every root its own square, while no square has more than one root and no root more than one square. But there are as many square roots as there are numbers, since every number is the square root of some square. He denied that this was fundamentally contradictory, however, he concluded that this meant we could not compare the sizes of infinite sets, missing the opportunity to discover cardinality.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Galilei |first=Galileo |author-link=Galileo Galilei |url=https://dn790007.ca.archive.org/0/items/dialoguesconcern00galiuoft/dialoguesconcern00galiuoft.pdf |title=Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences |publisher=[[The Macmillan Company]] |year=1914 |location=New York |pages=31–33 |language=en |translator-last=Crew |translator-first=Henry |orig-year=1638 |translator-last2=De Salvio |translator-first2=Alfonso}}</ref> |
|||
[[Bernard Bolzano]]'s ''[[Paradoxes of the Infinite]]'' (''Paradoxien des Unendlichen'', 1851) is often considered the first systematic attempt to introduce the concept of sets into [[mathematical analysis]]. In this work, Bolzano defended the notion of [[actual infinity]], examined various properties of infinite collections, including an early formulation of what would later be recognized as one-to-one correspondence between infinite sets, and proposed to base mathematics on a notion similar to sets. He discussed examples such as the pairing between the [[Interval (mathematics)|intervals]] <math>[0,5]</math> and <math>[0,12]</math> by the relation <math>5y = 12x.</math> Bolzano also revisited and extended Galileo's paradox. However, he too resisted saying that these sets were, in that sense, the same size. Thus, while ''Paradoxes of the Infinite'' anticipated several ideas central to later set theory, the work had little influence on contemporary mathematics, in part due to its [[posthumous publication]] and limited circulation.<ref>{{Citation |last=Ferreirós |first=José |title=The Early Development of Set Theory |date=2024 |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/settheory-early/ |access-date=2025-01-04 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210512135148/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/settheory-early/ |archive-date=2021-05-12 |url-status=live |edition=Winter 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Bolzano |first=Bernard |title=Einleitung zur Größenlehre und erste Begriffe der allgemeinen Größenlehre |volume=II, A, 7 |page=152 |year=1975 |editor-last=Berg |editor-first=Jan |series=Bernard-Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe, edited by Eduard Winter et al. |location=Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt |publisher=Friedrich Frommann Verlag |isbn=3-7728-0466-7 |author-link=Bernard Bolzano}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Bolzano |first=Bernard |url=https://archive.org/details/dli.ernet.503861/ |title=Paradoxes Of The Infinite |date=1950 |publisher=Routledge and Kegan Paul |location=London |translator-last=Prihonsky |translator-first=Fr.}}</ref> |
|||
===Cardinality of the continuum=== |
|||
{{main|Cardinality of the continuum|Continuum hypothesis}} |
|||
[[File:Number line.png|thumb|The [[number line]], containing all points in its continuum.|314x314px]] |
|||
The [[number line]] is a geometric construct of the intuitive notions of "[[space]]" and "[[distance]]" wherein each point corresponds to a distinct quantity or position along a continuous path. The terms "continuum" and "continuous" refer to the totality of this line, having some space (other points) between any two points on the line ([[Dense order|dense]] and [[Archimedean property|archimedian]]) and the absence of any gaps ([[Completeness of the real numbers|completeness]]), This intuitive construct is formalized by the set of [[real numbers]] <math>(\R)</math> which model the continuum as a complete, densely ordered, uncountable set. |
|||
[[File:Cantor set binary tree.svg|thumb|262x262px|First five itterations approaching the Cantor set]] |
|||
The [[cardinality of the continuum]], denoted by "<math>\mathfrak c</math>" (a lowercase [[fraktur (script)|fraktur script]] "c"), remains invariant under various transformations and mappings, many considered surprising. For example, all intervals on the real line e.g. <math>[0,1]</math>, and <math>[0,2]</math>, have the same cardinality as the entire set <math>\R</math>. First, <math>f(x) = 2x</math> is a bijection from <math>[0,1]</math> to <math>[0,2]</math>. Then, the [[tangent function]] is a bijection from the interval <math display="inline">\left( \frac{-\pi}{2} \, , \frac{\pi}{2} \right)</math> to the whole real line. A more surprising example is the [[Cantor set]], which is defined as follows: take the interval <math>[0,1]</math> and remove the middle third <math display="inline">\left( \frac{1}{3}, \frac{2}{3} \right)</math>, then remove the middle third of each of the two remaining segments, and continue removing middle thirds (see image). The Cantor set is the set of points that survive this process. This set that remains is all of the points whose decimal expansion can be written in [[Ternary numeral system|ternary]] without a 1. Reinterpreting these decimal expansions as [[Binary number|binary]] (e.g. by replacing the 2s with 1s) gives a bijection between the Cantor set and the interval <math>[0,1]</math>. |
|||
[[File:Peanocurve.svg|thumb|339x339px|Three iterations of a [[Peano curve]] construction, whose [[Limit of a sequence|limit]] is a [[space-filling curve]].]] |
|||
[[Space-filling curves]] are continuous surjective maps from the [[unit interval]] <math>[0,1]</math> onto the [[unit square]] on <math>\R^2</math>, with classical examples such as the [[Peano curve]] and [[Hilbert curve]]. Although such maps are not injective, they are indeed surjective, and thus suffice to demonstrate cardinal equivalence. They can be reused at each dimension to show that <math>|\R| = |\R^n| = \mathfrak{c}</math> for any dimension <math>n \geq 1.</math> The infinite [[cartesian product]] <math>\R^\infty</math>, can also be shown to have cardinality <math>\mathfrak c</math>. This can be established by cardinal exponentiation: <math>|\R^\infty| = \mathfrak{c}^{\aleph_0} = \left(2^{\aleph_0} \right)^{\aleph_0} = 2^{(\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0)} = 2^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak{c} = |\R|</math>. Thus, the real numbers, all finite-dimensional real spaces, and the countable cartesian product share the same cardinality. |
|||
Other, more minor contributions include [[David Hume]] in ''[[A Treatise of Human Nature]]'' (1739), who said ''"When two numbers are so combined, as that the one has always a unit answering to every unit of the other, we pronounce them equal",<ref>{{cite book |last=Hume |first=David |date=1739–1740 |title=A Treatise of Human Nature |chapter=Part III. Of Knowledge and Probability: Sect. I. Of Knowledge |chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0021 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>'' now called ''[[Hume's principle]]'', which was used extensively by [[Gottlob Frege]] later during the rise of set theory.<ref>{{cite book |last=Frege |first=Gottlob |date=1884 |title=Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik |chapter=IV. Der Begriff der Anzahl § 63. Die Möglichkeit der eindeutigen Zuordnung als solches. Logisches Bedenken, dass die Gleichheit für diesen Fall besonders erklärt wird |quote=§63. Ein solches Mittel nennt schon Hume: »Wenn zwei Zahlen so combinirt werden, dass die eine immer eine Einheit hat, die jeder Einheit der andern entspricht, so geben wir sie als gleich an.« |chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/48312/pg48312-images.html#para_63 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref> [[Jakob Steiner]], whom [[Georg Cantor]] credits the original term, ''Mächtigkeit'', for cardinality (1867).<ref name=":2" /><ref name=":3" /><ref name=":4" /> [[Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet]] is commonly credited for being the first to explicitly formulate the [[pigeonhole principle]] in 1834,<ref>Jeff Miller, Peter Flor, Gunnar Berg, and Julio González Cabillón. "[http://jeff560.tripod.com/p.html Pigeonhole principle]". In Jeff Miller (ed.) ''[http://jeff560.tripod.com/mathword.html Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics]''. Electronic document, retrieved November 11, 2006</ref> though it was used at least two centuries earlier by [[Jean Leurechon]] in 1624.<ref name="leurechon">{{cite journal |last1=Rittaud |first1=Benoît |last2=Heeffer |first2=Albrecht |year=2014 |title=The pigeonhole principle, two centuries before Dirichlet |url=https://biblio.ugent.be/publication/4115264 |journal=The Mathematical Intelligencer |volume=36 |issue=2 |pages=27–29 |doi=10.1007/s00283-013-9389-1 |mr=3207654 |s2cid=44193229 |hdl-access=free |hdl=1854/LU-4115264}}</ref> |
|||
As shown in {{slink||Unountable sets}}, the set of real numbers is strictly larger than the set of natural numbers. Specifically, <math>|\R| = |\mathcal{P}(\N)| </math>. The [[Continuum Hypothesis]] (CH) asserts that the real numbers have the next largest cardinality after the natural numbers, that is <math>|\R| = \aleph_1</math>. As shown by [[Kurt Gödel|Gödel]] and [[Paul Cohen|Cohen]], the continuum hypothesis is [[independence (mathematical logic)|independent]] of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice|ZFC]], a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is [[Consistency|consistent]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=Paul J. |date=December 15, 1963 |title=The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=50 |issue=6 |pages=1143–1148 |bibcode=1963PNAS...50.1143C |doi=10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 |jstor=71858 |pmc=221287 |pmid=16578557 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=Paul J. |date=January 15, 1964 |title=The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=51 |issue=1 |pages=105–110 |bibcode=1964PNAS...51..105C |doi=10.1073/pnas.51.1.105 |jstor=72252 |pmc=300611 |pmid=16591132 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Penrose |first=R |title=The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe |year=2005 |publisher=Vintage Books |isbn=0-09-944068-7 |author-link=Roger Penrose}}</ref> The [[Generalized Continuum Hypothesis]] (GCH) extends this to all infinite cardinals, stating that <math>2^{\aleph_\alpha} = \aleph_{\alpha+1}</math> for every ordinal <math>\alpha</math>. Without GHC, the cardinality of <math>\R</math> cannot be written in terms of alephs. The [[Beth numbers]] provide a concise notation for powersets of the real numbers starting from <math>\beth_1 = |\R|</math>, then <math>\beth_2 = |\mathcal{P}(\R)| = 2^{\beth_1}</math>, and in general <math>\beth_{n+1} = 2^{\beth_n}</math>. |
|||
=== Early set theory === |
|||
==== Georg Cantor ==== |
|||
[[File:Georg_Cantor3.jpg|alt=refer to caption|thumb|339x339px|[[Georg Cantor]], {{spaces|4|hair}}{{circa}} 1870]] |
|||
The concept of cardinality, as a formal measure of the size of a set, emerged nearly fully formed in the work of Georg Cantor during the 1870s and 1880s, in the context of [[mathematical analysis]]. In a series of papers beginning with ''[[Cantor's first set theory article|On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers]]'' (1874),<ref>{{Citation |last=Cantor |first=Herrn |title=Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen |date=1984 |work=Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfaltigkeiten: Arbeiten zur Mengenlehre aus den Jahren 1872–1884 |series=Teubner-Archiv zur Mathematik |volume=2 |pages=19–24 |editor-last=Cantor |editor-first=Georg |orig-date=1874 |url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-7091-9516-1_2 |access-date=2025-05-24 |place=Vienna |publisher=Springer |language=de |doi=10.1007/978-3-7091-9516-1_2 |isbn=978-3-7091-9516-1}}</ref> Cantor introduced the idea of comparing the sizes of infinite sets, through the notion of one-to-one correspondence. He showed that the set of [[real numbers]] was, in this sense, strictly larger than the set of natural numbers [[Cantor's first set theory article#Second theorem|using a nested intervals argument]]. This result was later refined into the more widely known [[Cantor's diagonal argument|diagonal argument]] of 1891, published in ''Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,''<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1890 |title=Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigketislehre. |url=https://eudml.org/doc/144383 |journal=Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung |volume=1 |pages=72–78 |issn=0012-0456}}</ref> where he also proved the more general result (now called [[Cantor's Theorem]]) that the [[power set]] of any set is strictly larger than the set itself. |
|||
Cantor introduced the notion [[cardinal numbers]] in terms of [[ordinal numbers]]. He viewed cardinal numbers as an abstraction of sets, introduced the notations, where, for a given set <math display="inline">M</math>, the [[order type]] of that set was written <math display="inline">\overline{M}</math>, and the cardinal number was <span style="border-top: 3px double;"><math display="inline">M</math></span>, a double abstraction. He also introduced the [[#Aleph numbers|Aleph sequence]] for infinite cardinal numbers. These notations appeared in correspondence and were formalized in his later writings, particularly the series ''Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre'' (1895{{En dash}}1897).<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1895-11-01 |title=Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre |url=https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/BF02124929 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=de |volume=46 |issue=4 |pages=481–512 |doi=10.1007/BF02124929 |issn=1432-1807}}</ref> In these works, Cantor developed an [[Cardinal arithmetic|arithmetic of cardinal numbers]], defining addition, multiplication, and exponentiation of cardinal numbers based on set-theoretic constructions. This led to the formulation of the [[Continuum Hypothesis]] (CH), the proposition that no set has cardinality strictly between <math>\aleph_0</math> and the [[cardinality of the continuum]], that is <math>|\R| = \aleph_1</math>. Cantor was unable to resolve CH and left it as an [[open problem]]. |
|||
==== Other contributors ==== |
|||
Parallel to Cantor’s development, [[Richard Dedekind]] independently formulated [[Dedekind-infinite set|a definition of infinite set]] as one that can be placed in bijection with a proper subset of itself, which was shown to be equivalent with Cantor’s definition of cardinality (given the [[axiom of choice]]). Dedekind’s ''[[Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?]]'' (1888) emphasized structural properties over extensional definitions, and supported the bijective formulation of size and number. Dedekind was in correspondence with Cantor during the development of set theory; he supplied Cantor with a proof of the countability of the [[algebraic numbers]], and gave feedback and modifications on Cantor's proofs before publishing. |
|||
After Cantor's 1883 proof that all finite-dimensional spaces <math>(\R^n)</math> have the same cardinality,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cantor |first=Georg |date=1883-12-01 |title=Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01446819 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=de |volume=21 |issue=4 |pages=545–591 |doi=10.1007/BF01446819 |issn=1432-1807}}</ref> in 1890, [[Giuseppe Peano]] introduced the [[Peano curve]], which was a more visual proof that the [[unit interval]] <math>[0,1]</math> has the same cardinality as the [[unit square]] on <math>\R^2.</math><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Peano |first=G. |date=1890-03-01 |title=Sur une courbe, qui remplit toute une aire plane |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01199438 |journal=Mathematische Annalen |language=fr |volume=36 |issue=1 |pages=157–160 |doi=10.1007/BF01199438 |issn=1432-1807 |archive-url=https://archive.org/details/PeanoSurUneCurve |archive-date=2018-07-22}}</ref> This created a new area of mathematical analysis studying what is now called [[space-filling curves]].<ref>{{citation |last=Gugenheimer |first=Heinrich Walter |title=Differential Geometry |page=3 |year=1963 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CSYtkV4NTioC&pg=PA |publisher=Courier Dover Publications |isbn=9780486157207}}.</ref> |
|||
German logician [[Gottlob Frege]] attempted to ground the concepts of number and arithmetic in logic using Cantor's theory of cardinality and [[Hume's principle]] in ''[[Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik]]'' (1884) and the subsequent ''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'' (1893, 1903). Frege defined cardinal numbers as [[equivalence classes]] of sets under equinumerosity. However, Frege's approach to set theory was later shown to be flawed. His approach was eventually reformalized by [[Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation|Bertrand Russell]] and [[Alfred North Whitehead|Alfred Whitehead]] in ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (1910{{En dash}}1913, vol. II){{Sfn|Russell|Whitehead}} using a [[Type theory#History|theory of types]]. Though Russell initially had difficulties understanding Cantor's and Frege’s intuitions of cardinality.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Russell |first=B. |date=1907 |title=On Some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types |url=https://londmathsoc.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29?doi=10.1112%2Fplms%2Fs2-4.1.29 |journal=Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society |language=en |volume=s2-4 |issue=1 |pages=29–53 |doi=10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29 |issn=1460-244X}}</ref> This definition of cardinal numbers is now referred to as the ''Frege-Russell'' definition. |
|||
=== Axiomatic set theory === |
|||
{{Multiple image |
|||
| image1 = Ernst Zermelo 1900s.jpg |
|||
| image2 = Kurt gödel.jpg |
|||
| total_width = 350 |
|||
| footer = [[Ernst Zermelo]] and [[Kurt Gödel]] |
|||
}} |
|||
In 1908, [[Ernst Zermelo]] proposed the first [[axiomatization]] of set theory, now called [[Zermelo set theory]], primarily to support his earlier (1904) proof of the [[Well-ordering theorem]], which showed that all cardinal numbers could be represented as [[#Aleph numbers|Alephs]], though the proof required a controversial principle now known as the [[Axiom of Choice]] (AC). Zermelo's system would later be extended by [[Abraham Fraenkel]] and [[Thoralf Skolem]] in the 1920s to create the standard foundation of set theory, called [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] (ZFC, "C" for the Axiom of Choice). ZFC provided a rigorous, albeit non-[[Categorical theory|categorical]], foundation through which infinite cardinals could be systematically studied while avoiding the [[Paradoxes of set theory|paradoxes of naive set theory]]. |
|||
In 1940, [[Kurt Gödel]] showed that CH cannot be ''disproved'' from ZF set theory (ZFC without Choice), even if the axiom of choice is adopted, i.e. from ZFC. Gödel's proof shows that both CH and AC hold in the [[constructible universe]], an [[inner model]] of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are (relatively) [[consistent]] with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gödel |first1=Kurt |date=1938 |title=The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |volume=24 |issue=12 |pages=556–557 |bibcode=1938PNAS...24..556G |doi=10.1073/pnas.24.12.556 |pmc=1077160 |pmid=16577857 |doi-access=free}}</ref> In 1963, [[Paul Cohen]] showed that CH cannot be ''proven'' from the ZFC axioms, which showed that CH was [[Independence (mathematical logic)|independent]] from ZFC. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of [[Forcing (mathematics)|forcing]], which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZFC in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the [[Fields Medal]] in 1966 for his proof.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cohen |first=P. J. |date=1963 |title=THE INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS |url=https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC221287/ |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=50 |issue=6 |pages=1143–1148 |doi=10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=221287 |pmid=16578557}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Cohen |first=Paul Joseph |author-link=Paul Cohen (mathematician) |title=Set theory and the continuum hypothesis |date=2008 |publisher=Dover Publications |isbn=978-0-486-46921-8 |location=Mineola, New York City |orig-date=1966}}</ref> |
|||
== Paradoxes == |
=== Paradoxes === |
||
During the rise of set theory, several [[paradoxes]] (see: ''[[Paradoxes of set theory]]''). These can be divided into two kinds: ''real paradoxes'' and ''apparent paradoxes''. Apparent paradoxes are those which follow a series of reasonable steps and arrive at a conclusion which seems impossible or incorrect according to one's [[intuition]], but aren't necessarily logically impossible. Two historical examples have been given, ''Galileo's Paradox'' and ''Aristotle's Wheel'', in {{Section link|2=History|nopage=y}}. Real paradoxes are those which, through reasonable steps, prove a [[Contradiction|logical contradiction]]. The real paradoxes here apply to [[naive set theory]] or otherwise informal statements, and have been resolved by restating the problem in terms of a [[Set theory#Formalized set theory|formalized set theory]], such as [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]]. |
During the rise of set theory, several [[paradoxes]] (see: ''[[Paradoxes of set theory]]''). These can be divided into two kinds: ''real paradoxes'' and ''apparent paradoxes''. Apparent paradoxes are those which follow a series of reasonable steps and arrive at a conclusion which seems impossible or incorrect according to one's [[intuition]], but aren't necessarily logically impossible. Two historical examples have been given, ''Galileo's Paradox'' and ''Aristotle's Wheel'', in {{Section link|2=History|nopage=y}}. Real paradoxes are those which, through reasonable steps, prove a [[Contradiction|logical contradiction]]. The real paradoxes here apply to [[naive set theory]] or otherwise informal statements, and have been resolved by restating the problem in terms of a [[Set theory#Formalized set theory|formalized set theory]], such as [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]]. |
||
=== Apparent paradoxes === |
==== Apparent paradoxes ==== |
||
==== Hilbert's hotel ==== |
===== Hilbert's hotel ===== |
||
{{Main|Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel}} |
{{Main|Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel}} |
||
[[File:Hilbert's Hotel.png|thumb|259x259px|Visual representation of Hilbert's hotel]] |
[[File:Hilbert's Hotel.png|thumb|259x259px|Visual representation of Hilbert's hotel]] |
||
Line 206: | Line 225: | ||
Then, the scenario continues by imagining an infinite bus of new guests seeking a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the person in room 1 to room 2, room 2 to room 4, and in general, room n to room 2n. Thus, all the even-numbered rooms are occupied, but all the odd-numbered rooms are vacant, leaving room for the infinite bus of new guests. The scenario continues by assuming an infinite number of these infinite buses arrive at the hotel, and showing that the hotel is still able to accommodate. Finally, an infinite bus which has a seat for every [[real number]] arrives, and the hotel is no longer able to accommodate.<ref name=":5" /> |
Then, the scenario continues by imagining an infinite bus of new guests seeking a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the person in room 1 to room 2, room 2 to room 4, and in general, room n to room 2n. Thus, all the even-numbered rooms are occupied, but all the odd-numbered rooms are vacant, leaving room for the infinite bus of new guests. The scenario continues by assuming an infinite number of these infinite buses arrive at the hotel, and showing that the hotel is still able to accommodate. Finally, an infinite bus which has a seat for every [[real number]] arrives, and the hotel is no longer able to accommodate.<ref name=":5" /> |
||
==== Skolem's paradox ==== |
===== Skolem's paradox ===== |
||
{{Main|Skolem's paradox}} |
{{Main|Skolem's paradox}} |
||
[[File:Lowenheim-skolem.svg|thumb|Illustration of the [[Löwenheim–Skolem theorem]], where <math>\mathcal{M}</math> and <math>\mathcal{N}</math> are models of set theory, and <math>\kappa</math> is an arbitrary infinite cardinal number.]] |
[[File:Lowenheim-skolem.svg|thumb|Illustration of the [[Löwenheim–Skolem theorem]], where <math>\mathcal{M}</math> and <math>\mathcal{N}</math> are models of set theory, and <math>\kappa</math> is an arbitrary infinite cardinal number.]] |
||
Line 213: | Line 232: | ||
A mathematical explanation of the paradox, showing that it is not a true contradiction in mathematics, was first given in 1922 by [[Thoralf Skolem]]. He explained that the countability of a set is not absolute, but relative to the model in which the cardinality is measured. Skolem's work was harshly received by [[Ernst Zermelo]], who argued against the limitations of first-order logic and Skolem's notion of "relativity", but the result quickly came to be accepted by the mathematical community.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=van Dalen |first1=Dirk |author-link1=Dirk van Dalen |last2=Ebbinghaus |first2=Heinz-Dieter |author2-link=Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus |date=Jun 2000 |title=Zermelo and the Skolem Paradox |url=https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/document?repid=rep1&type=pdf&doi=9d51449b161b9e1d352e103af28fe07f5e15cb4b |journal=The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic |volume=6 |pages=145–161 |citeseerx=10.1.1.137.3354 |doi=10.2307/421203 |jstor=421203 |s2cid=8530810 |number=2 |hdl=1874/27769}}</ref><ref name=":6" /> |
A mathematical explanation of the paradox, showing that it is not a true contradiction in mathematics, was first given in 1922 by [[Thoralf Skolem]]. He explained that the countability of a set is not absolute, but relative to the model in which the cardinality is measured. Skolem's work was harshly received by [[Ernst Zermelo]], who argued against the limitations of first-order logic and Skolem's notion of "relativity", but the result quickly came to be accepted by the mathematical community.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=van Dalen |first1=Dirk |author-link1=Dirk van Dalen |last2=Ebbinghaus |first2=Heinz-Dieter |author2-link=Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus |date=Jun 2000 |title=Zermelo and the Skolem Paradox |url=https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/document?repid=rep1&type=pdf&doi=9d51449b161b9e1d352e103af28fe07f5e15cb4b |journal=The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic |volume=6 |pages=145–161 |citeseerx=10.1.1.137.3354 |doi=10.2307/421203 |jstor=421203 |s2cid=8530810 |number=2 |hdl=1874/27769}}</ref><ref name=":6" /> |
||
=== Real paradoxes === |
==== Real paradoxes ==== |
||
==== Cantor's paradox ==== |
===== Cantor's paradox ===== |
||
{{Main|Cantor's paradox}} |
{{Main|Cantor's paradox}} |
||
[[Cantor's theorem]] state's that, for any set <math>A,</math> possibly infinite, its [[powerset]] <math>\mathcal{P}(A)</math> has a strictly greater cardinality. For example, this means there is no bijection from <math>\N</math> to <math>\mathcal{P}(\N) \sim \R.</math> [[Cantor's paradox]] is a paradox in [[naive set theory]], which shows that there cannot exist a "set of all sets" or "[[Universe (mathematics)|universe set]]". It starts by assuming there is some set of all sets, <math>U := \{x \; | \; x \,\text{ is a set} \},</math> then it must be that <math>U</math> is strictly smaller than <math>\mathcal{P}(U),</math> thus <math>|U| \leq |\mathcal{P}(U)| .</math> But since <math>U</math> contains all sets, we must have that <math>\mathcal{P}(U) \subseteq U,</math> and thus <math>|\mathcal{P}(U)| \leq |U|.</math> Therefore <math>|\mathcal{P}(U)| = |U|,</math> contradicting Cantor's theorem. This was one of the original paradoxes that added to the need for a formalized set theory to avoid these paradoxes. This paradox is usually resolved in formal set theories by disallowing [[unrestricted comprehension]] and the existence of a universe set. |
[[Cantor's theorem]] state's that, for any set <math>A,</math> possibly infinite, its [[powerset]] <math>\mathcal{P}(A)</math> has a strictly greater cardinality. For example, this means there is no bijection from <math>\N</math> to <math>\mathcal{P}(\N) \sim \R.</math> [[Cantor's paradox]] is a paradox in [[naive set theory]], which shows that there cannot exist a "set of all sets" or "[[Universe (mathematics)|universe set]]". It starts by assuming there is some set of all sets, <math>U := \{x \; | \; x \,\text{ is a set} \},</math> then it must be that <math>U</math> is strictly smaller than <math>\mathcal{P}(U),</math> thus <math>|U| \leq |\mathcal{P}(U)| .</math> But since <math>U</math> contains all sets, we must have that <math>\mathcal{P}(U) \subseteq U,</math> and thus <math>|\mathcal{P}(U)| \leq |U|.</math> Therefore <math>|\mathcal{P}(U)| = |U|,</math> contradicting Cantor's theorem. This was one of the original paradoxes that added to the need for a formalized set theory to avoid these paradoxes. This paradox is usually resolved in formal set theories by disallowing [[unrestricted comprehension]] and the existence of a universe set. |
||
==== Set of all cardinal numbers ==== |
===== Set of all cardinal numbers ===== |
||
Similar to Cantor's paradox, the paradox of the set of all cardinal numbers is a result due to unrestricted comprehension. It often uses the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinal numbers for representatives. It is related to the [[Burali-Forti paradox]]. It begins by assuming there is some set <math>S := \{ X \, | X \text{ is a cardinal number}\}.</math> Then, if there is some largest element <math>\aleph \in S ,</math> then the powerset <math>\mathcal{P}(\aleph)</math> is strictly greater, and thus not in <math>S.</math> Conversly, if there is no largest element, then the [[Union (set theory)#Arbitrary union|union]] <math>\bigcup S</math> contains the elements of all elements of <math>S,</math> and is therefore greater than or equal to each element. Since there is no largest element in <math>S,</math> for any element <math>x \in S,</math> there is another element <math>y \in S</math> such that <math>|x| < |y|</math> and <math>|y| \leq \Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr|.</math> Thus, for any <math>x \in S,</math> <math>|x| < \Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr|,</math> and so <math>\Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr| \notin S.</math> |
Similar to Cantor's paradox, the paradox of the set of all cardinal numbers is a result due to unrestricted comprehension. It often uses the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinal numbers for representatives. It is related to the [[Burali-Forti paradox]]. It begins by assuming there is some set <math>S := \{ X \, | X \text{ is a cardinal number}\}.</math> Then, if there is some largest element <math>\aleph \in S ,</math> then the powerset <math>\mathcal{P}(\aleph)</math> is strictly greater, and thus not in <math>S.</math> Conversly, if there is no largest element, then the [[Union (set theory)#Arbitrary union|union]] <math>\bigcup S</math> contains the elements of all elements of <math>S,</math> and is therefore greater than or equal to each element. Since there is no largest element in <math>S,</math> for any element <math>x \in S,</math> there is another element <math>y \in S</math> such that <math>|x| < |y|</math> and <math>|y| \leq \Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr|.</math> Thus, for any <math>x \in S,</math> <math>|x| < \Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr|,</math> and so <math>\Bigl| \bigcup S \Bigr| \notin S.</math> |
||
Line 238: | Line 257: | ||
==References== |
==References== |
||
===Notes=== |
|||
{{notelist}} |
|||
=== Citations === |
=== Citations === |
||
{{reflist}} |
{{reflist}} |
||
{{notelist}} |
|||
=== Bibliography === |
=== Bibliography === |
Revision as of 16:26, 17 June 2025
![]() | It has been suggested that Equinumerosity be merged into this article. (Discuss) Proposed since May 2025. |

In mathematics, the cardinality of a finite set is the number of its elements, and is therefore a measure of size of the set. Since the discovery by Georg Cantor, in the late 19th century, of different sizes of infinite sets, the term cardinality was coined for generalizing to infinite sets the concept of the number of elements.
More precisely, two sets have the same cardinality if there exists a one-to-one correspondence between them. In the case of finite sets, the common operation of counting consists of establishing a one-to-one correspondence between a given set and the set of the first natural numbers, for some natural number . In this case, is the cardinality of the set.
A set is infinite if the counting operation never finishes, that is, if its cardinality is not a natural number. The basic example of an infinite set is the set of all natural numbers.
The great discovery of Cantor is that infinite sets of apparently different size may have the same cardinality, and, nevertheless, there are infinitely many different cardinalities. For example, the even numbers, the prime numbers and the polynomials whose coefficients are rational number have the same cardinality as the natural numbers. The set of the real numbers has a greater cardinality than the natural numbers, and has the same cardinality as the interval and as every Euclidean space of any dimension. For every set, its power set (the set of all its subsets) has a greater cardinality.
Cardinalities are represented with cardinal numbers, which are specific sets of a given cardinality, which have been chosen once for all. Some infinite cardinalities have been given a specific name, such as for the cardinality of the natural numbers and , the cardinality of the continuum, for the cardinality of the real numbers.
Basics
Finite cardinalities
Given a finite set, its cardinality is what is commonly called its number of elements.
The standard way to compute this number of elements is by counting, that is, by labelling the set elements by the first natural numbers, with no gap and no repetition. Mathematically, counting amounts to construct a bijective function from the first natural numbers to the set to be counted.
The number of elements of a finite set is the largest natural number reached by counting its elements. So, a set has elements if there is a bijective function from the set to . One says that the cardinality of is . If the counting process never finishes, one has an infinite set.
A proof by induction is needed for proving that the result of counting does not depend on the order in which the elements are counted. This is expressed by the fact that, if there is no injective function, and thus no bijective function, from to A variant of this property is often referred to as the pigeonhole principle.
The latter poperty is equivalent with the fact that , if there is no surjective function from to This means that for finite sets, the fifth Euclid's common notion applies, which states that "the whole is greater than the part". This principle is not valid for infinite sets, and this is presumably the main reason for which most mathematicians were reluctant to study infinite sets, before the 20th century (see Galileo's paradox).
General case
Cardinalities, like natural numbers, are difficult to define formally, and this is by their basic properties that there are best introduced. Therefore, in this section, the cardinality of a set is not defined as a value, but only the comparison between cardinalities (equality and greater than) is defined and studied. (This is to compare with the natural numbers for which operations and ordering are defined a long time before any proper definition of the concept.)
The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number, the numbers of its elements, which is commonly denoted |S| or .[1] These notations are also used for infinite sets, although seems more common in the infinite case.[citation needed]
Equinumerosity
Two sets have the same cardinality or are equinumerous if there exists a bijection or one-to-one correspondence between them. For example, the integers and the even integers have the same cardinality, since multiplication and division by 2 provide bijection between them.
The equinumerosity of two sets and is denoted
For any three sets , , and , one has
- (reflexitivity),
- (symmetry),
- and (transitivity).
This results immediately from the fact that the identity function, the inverse function of a bijective function, and the composition of two bijective functions are all bijective. This means that equinumerosity is an equivalence relation on the subsets of a given set.[a]
See below for various examples.
Partial order
One says that the cardinality of a set is less than or equal to the cardinality of , denoted
if there is an injective function from to .
This defines a partial order on cardinalities, since one has
- ,
- and imply
- and inly .
The two first assertions result from the fact that the identity function and the composition of two injective functions are injective. The third assertion results from Schröder–Bernstein theorem, which asserts that, given an injection from into and an injection from into , one can construct a bijection between and .
If the axiom of choice is assumed, as it is commonly the case in modern mathematics, this partial order is a total order and a well-order.
Without the axiom of choice, one cannot prove that cadinalities are totally ordered. In particular, without the axiom of choice, there may exist Dedekind finite sets that are infinite; for such a set , one has neither nor .
Countable sets
As suggested by the name, a countable set is a set that can be exhausted by counting its elements, possibly with an endless counting. Such a counting process defines an injective function from the set to the natual numbers.
So, a countable set is a set such that . Thus, a countable set is either a finite set or a countably infinite set, that is a set such that .
Every subset of a countable set is countable.

Many sets that seem to be much larger that the natural numbers are neverthess countable. This is the case, in particular, of the set of all finite sequences of natural numbers. This can be proven by ordering these sequences as follows. Two sequences are first compared by the sums of their elements; when the sum of the members of two sequences are equal, the two sequences are compared by using a lexicographical order or any other total order. Since there is a finite number of sequences with a given sum, the order so defined provides a bijection between the the set of all finite sequences of natural numbers and the natural numbers.
It follows that countable sets include all sets whose all elements can be unambiguously encoded with sequences of natural numbers. This includes many algebraic structures such the integers (), the rational numbers (), the polynomials with rational coefficients () and algebraic numbers, which are all countably infinite sets.
The set of all algorithms is also countably infinite, and it results that the same is true for the set of computable numbers. Similarly, the set of the theorems of a mathematical theory is also countable.
Nevertheless, there are infinite sets that are not countable; see the next section.
Uncountable sets
There are sets that are not countable. They are said to be uncountable. That is, a uncountable set is an infinite set with a cardinality strictly larger than that of the set of the natural numbers.
Cardinality of the continuum
The first prof of the existence of uncountable sets was given by Georg Cantor in 1891, who proved that the interval of the real line is uncountable.[2]
In a second proof, he used what is now called Cantor's diagonal argument to prove that a function from the natural numbers to the interval cannot be surjective, and is therefore not a bijection. Indeed, if is such a function, one can define a number of the interval that is not of the form . Such a number is obtained with a number such that, for every , the th decimal digit of differs from the th digit of and differs also from anf (the latter condition for avoiding numbers that have two decimal representations). The term "diagonal argument" refers to the fact that, one can write an (infinite) matrix such the entry is the th digit of , and, then, the digits of are obtained by changing the digits of the diagonal of the matrix.[3] Then, this number will be different from each of the numbers in the list by at least one digit, and therefore must not be in the list. This shows that the real numbers cannot be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the naturals, and thus must be strictly larger.[4]
One has since the function is a bijection between these two sets.
This cardinality is called the cardinality of the continuum and commonly denoted as ("the continuum" is a old name for the real line).
Space-filling curves show that every finite dimensional real vector space has the cardinality of the continuum, as well as almost all spaces considered in geometry and analysis. So, almost all uncountable sets that are encountered in mathematics have the cardinality of the continuum.
Powersets
There are many other cardinalities than those described above. The most common method for defining sets with larger cardinalities is with powersets.
The powerset of a set is the set of all subsets of . It often identified with the set of all functions of to , through the one-to-one correspondence associating to such a function the subset where it takes the value .

The cardinality of is the cardinality of the continuum. This can be proven by considering the sequence of the digits of the binary representation of a real number in the interval as a function from to .
More generally, Cantor's theorem asserts that for every set , one has
This can be proved with a variant of Cantor's diagonal agument: one has since the map is an injective function from to . So, it suffices to prove that there is no bijection between and , and, in particular, that a function from to cannot be surjective.
So, let be a function from to . The subset cannot be in the image of , since if one would have then either or but not both. The definition of implies that if one is in any of the two cases, one is also in the other case, a contradiction that proves that is not surjective.
A transfinite induction using powerset construction and starting from the natural numbers allows giving values, called beth numbers, to some cardinalities. These beth numbers are uniquely defined sets defined by:
- for every ordinal
- for every limit ordinal
Unless if the generalized continuum hypothesis is assumed, not all cardinalities can be represented by beth numbers.
Continuum hypothesis
The continuum hypothesis is the assertion that there is no set such that . With the axiom of choice, the continuum hypothesis implies that the cardinal of the continuum is the least uncountable cardinal.
The proof of the continuum hypothesis was the first of the Hilbert's problems, stated in 1900.
In the framework of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF), Paul Cohen proved in 1963, that the continuum hypothesis is independent from the other axioms of set theory, with or without the axiom of choice. More precicely, if ZF is consistent (that is, not self contradictory), then both ZF with ths continuum hypothesis and ZF with the negation of the continuum hypothesis are consistent, and they remain consistent if either the axiom of choice or its negation are added to the theory.[5][6][7]
Cardinal numbers
In the preceding sections, the "cardinality" of a set was defined relationally. That is, the cardinalities of two sets can be compared, but the cardinality of a specific set was not defined as a mathematical object.
The first tentatives for defining cardinalities were to define them as equivalence classes for the relation "having the same cardinality". Unfortunately, this does not work beause these equivalence classes are not sets. So, the approach that has been eventually chosen is to define once for all specific sets, called cardinal numbers or aleph numbers, such that every set is equinumerous with exactly one cardinal number.
The definition of cardinal numbers involves a transfinite induction and uses ordinal numbers, which are well ordered sets such that every well-ordered set is order isomorphic to exactly one ordinal number.
The axiom of choice states that every set can be well ordered. This implies that, without the axiom of choice, there may be cardinalities that do not correspond to a cardinal number.
Formally, the infinite cardinal mumbers, also called aleph numbers because they are denoted with the Hebrew letter aleph, are defined as follows:
- ( is the least infinite ordinal)
- For every ordinal one defines as the least ordinal such that
- For every limit ordinal one define as the least ordinal such that for all
If one starts the transfinite induction with the empty set instead of , the first cardinal numbers become the von Neumann natural numbers.
History
Etymology
In English, the term cardinality originates from the post-classical Latin cardinalis, meaning "principal" or "chief", which derives from cardo, a noun meaning "hinge". In Latin, cardo referred to something central or pivotal, both literally and metaphorically. This concept of centrality passed into medieval Latin and then into English, where cardinal came to describe things considered to be, in some sense, fundamental, such as cardinal virtues, cardinal sins, cardinal directions, and (in the grammatical sense) cardinal numbers.[8][9] The last of which referred to numbers used for counting (e.g., one, two, three),[10] as opposed to ordinal numbers, which express order (e.g., first, second, third),[11] and nominal numbers used for labeling without meaning (e.g., jersey numbers and serial numbers).[12]
In mathematics, the notion of cardinality was first introduced by Georg Cantor in the late 19th century, wherein he used the used the term Mächtigkeit, which may be translated as "magnitude" or "power", though Cantor credited the term to a work by Jakob Steiner on projective geometry.[13][14][15] The terms cardinality and cardinal number were eventually adopted from the grammatical sense, and later translations would use these terms.[16][17]
Prehistory
A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.[18] Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as 40000 years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.[19] The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian mathematics and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.[20]
Ancient history

From the 6th century BCE, the writings of Greek philosophers, such as Anaximander, show hints of comparing infinite sets or shapes. While the Greeks considered notions of infinity, they viewed it as paradoxical and imperfect (cf. Zeno's paradoxes), often associating good and evil with finite and infinite.[21] Aristotle distinguished between the notions of actual infinity and potential infinity, arguing that Greek mathematicians understood the difference, and that they "do not need the [actual] infinite and do not use it."[22] The greek notion of number (αριθμός, arithmos) was used exclusively for a definite number of definite objects (i.e. finite numbers).[23] This would be codified in Euclid's Elements, where the fifth common notion states "The whole is greater than the part", often called the Euclidean principle. This principle would be the dominating philosophy in mathematics until the 19th century.[21][24]
Around the 4th century BCE, Jaina mathematics would be the first to discuss different sizes of infinity. They defined three major classes of number: enumerable (finite numbers), unenumerable (asamkhyata, roughly, countably infinite), and infinite (ananta). Then they had five classes of infinite numbers: infinite in one direction, infinite in both directions, infinite in area, infinite everywhere, and infinite perpetually.[25][26]
One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded in Aristotle's Mechanics (c. 350 BCE), known as Aristotle's wheel paradox. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as two concentric circles. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: the circumference of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length.[27] Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.[21]
Pre-Cantorian set theory
Galileo Galilei presented what was later coined Galileo's paradox in his book Two New Sciences (1638), where he attempts to show that infinite quantities cannot be called greater or less than one another. He presents the paradox roughly as follows: a square number is one which is the product of another number with itself, such as 4 and 9, which are the squares of 2 and 3, respectively. Then the square root of a square number is that multiplicand. He then notes that there are as many square numbers as there are square roots, since every square has its own root and every root its own square, while no square has more than one root and no root more than one square. But there are as many square roots as there are numbers, since every number is the square root of some square. He denied that this was fundamentally contradictory, however, he concluded that this meant we could not compare the sizes of infinite sets, missing the opportunity to discover cardinality.[28]
Bernard Bolzano's Paradoxes of the Infinite (Paradoxien des Unendlichen, 1851) is often considered the first systematic attempt to introduce the concept of sets into mathematical analysis. In this work, Bolzano defended the notion of actual infinity, examined various properties of infinite collections, including an early formulation of what would later be recognized as one-to-one correspondence between infinite sets, and proposed to base mathematics on a notion similar to sets. He discussed examples such as the pairing between the intervals and by the relation Bolzano also revisited and extended Galileo's paradox. However, he too resisted saying that these sets were, in that sense, the same size. Thus, while Paradoxes of the Infinite anticipated several ideas central to later set theory, the work had little influence on contemporary mathematics, in part due to its posthumous publication and limited circulation.[29][30][31]
Other, more minor contributions include David Hume in A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), who said "When two numbers are so combined, as that the one has always a unit answering to every unit of the other, we pronounce them equal",[32] now called Hume's principle, which was used extensively by Gottlob Frege later during the rise of set theory.[33] Jakob Steiner, whom Georg Cantor credits the original term, Mächtigkeit, for cardinality (1867).[13][14][15] Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet is commonly credited for being the first to explicitly formulate the pigeonhole principle in 1834,[34] though it was used at least two centuries earlier by Jean Leurechon in 1624.[35]
Early set theory
Georg Cantor

The concept of cardinality, as a formal measure of the size of a set, emerged nearly fully formed in the work of Georg Cantor during the 1870s and 1880s, in the context of mathematical analysis. In a series of papers beginning with On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers (1874),[36] Cantor introduced the idea of comparing the sizes of infinite sets, through the notion of one-to-one correspondence. He showed that the set of real numbers was, in this sense, strictly larger than the set of natural numbers using a nested intervals argument. This result was later refined into the more widely known diagonal argument of 1891, published in Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,[37] where he also proved the more general result (now called Cantor's Theorem) that the power set of any set is strictly larger than the set itself.
Cantor introduced the notion cardinal numbers in terms of ordinal numbers. He viewed cardinal numbers as an abstraction of sets, introduced the notations, where, for a given set , the order type of that set was written , and the cardinal number was , a double abstraction. He also introduced the Aleph sequence for infinite cardinal numbers. These notations appeared in correspondence and were formalized in his later writings, particularly the series Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (1895–1897).[38] In these works, Cantor developed an arithmetic of cardinal numbers, defining addition, multiplication, and exponentiation of cardinal numbers based on set-theoretic constructions. This led to the formulation of the Continuum Hypothesis (CH), the proposition that no set has cardinality strictly between and the cardinality of the continuum, that is . Cantor was unable to resolve CH and left it as an open problem.
Other contributors
Parallel to Cantor’s development, Richard Dedekind independently formulated a definition of infinite set as one that can be placed in bijection with a proper subset of itself, which was shown to be equivalent with Cantor’s definition of cardinality (given the axiom of choice). Dedekind’s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? (1888) emphasized structural properties over extensional definitions, and supported the bijective formulation of size and number. Dedekind was in correspondence with Cantor during the development of set theory; he supplied Cantor with a proof of the countability of the algebraic numbers, and gave feedback and modifications on Cantor's proofs before publishing.
After Cantor's 1883 proof that all finite-dimensional spaces have the same cardinality,[39] in 1890, Giuseppe Peano introduced the Peano curve, which was a more visual proof that the unit interval has the same cardinality as the unit square on [40] This created a new area of mathematical analysis studying what is now called space-filling curves.[41]
German logician Gottlob Frege attempted to ground the concepts of number and arithmetic in logic using Cantor's theory of cardinality and Hume's principle in Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik (1884) and the subsequent Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (1893, 1903). Frege defined cardinal numbers as equivalence classes of sets under equinumerosity. However, Frege's approach to set theory was later shown to be flawed. His approach was eventually reformalized by Bertrand Russell and Alfred Whitehead in Principia Mathematica (1910–1913, vol. II)[42] using a theory of types. Though Russell initially had difficulties understanding Cantor's and Frege’s intuitions of cardinality.[43] This definition of cardinal numbers is now referred to as the Frege-Russell definition.
Axiomatic set theory
In 1908, Ernst Zermelo proposed the first axiomatization of set theory, now called Zermelo set theory, primarily to support his earlier (1904) proof of the Well-ordering theorem, which showed that all cardinal numbers could be represented as Alephs, though the proof required a controversial principle now known as the Axiom of Choice (AC). Zermelo's system would later be extended by Abraham Fraenkel and Thoralf Skolem in the 1920s to create the standard foundation of set theory, called Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC, "C" for the Axiom of Choice). ZFC provided a rigorous, albeit non-categorical, foundation through which infinite cardinals could be systematically studied while avoiding the paradoxes of naive set theory.
In 1940, Kurt Gödel showed that CH cannot be disproved from ZF set theory (ZFC without Choice), even if the axiom of choice is adopted, i.e. from ZFC. Gödel's proof shows that both CH and AC hold in the constructible universe, an inner model of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are (relatively) consistent with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent.[44] In 1963, Paul Cohen showed that CH cannot be proven from the ZFC axioms, which showed that CH was independent from ZFC. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of forcing, which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZFC in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the Fields Medal in 1966 for his proof.[45][46]
Paradoxes
During the rise of set theory, several paradoxes (see: Paradoxes of set theory). These can be divided into two kinds: real paradoxes and apparent paradoxes. Apparent paradoxes are those which follow a series of reasonable steps and arrive at a conclusion which seems impossible or incorrect according to one's intuition, but aren't necessarily logically impossible. Two historical examples have been given, Galileo's Paradox and Aristotle's Wheel, in § History. Real paradoxes are those which, through reasonable steps, prove a logical contradiction. The real paradoxes here apply to naive set theory or otherwise informal statements, and have been resolved by restating the problem in terms of a formalized set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.
Apparent paradoxes
Hilbert's hotel

Hilbert's Hotel is a thought experiment devised by the German mathematician David Hilbert to illustrate a counterintuitive property of countably infinite sets, allowing them to have the same cardinality as a proper subset of themselves. The scenario begins by imagining a hotel with an infinite number of rooms, all of which are occupied. But then a new guest walks in asking for a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the occupant of room 1 to room 2, the occupant of room 2 to room 3, room three to room 4, and in general, room n to room n+1. Then every guest still has a room, but room 1 opens up for the new guest.[47]
Then, the scenario continues by imagining an infinite bus of new guests seeking a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the person in room 1 to room 2, room 2 to room 4, and in general, room n to room 2n. Thus, all the even-numbered rooms are occupied, but all the odd-numbered rooms are vacant, leaving room for the infinite bus of new guests. The scenario continues by assuming an infinite number of these infinite buses arrive at the hotel, and showing that the hotel is still able to accommodate. Finally, an infinite bus which has a seat for every real number arrives, and the hotel is no longer able to accommodate.[47]
Skolem's paradox

In model theory, a model corresponds to a specific interpretation of a formal language or theory. It consists of a domain (a set of objects) and an interpretation of the symbols and formulas in the language, such that the axioms of the theory are satisfied within this structure. The Löwenheim–Skolem theorem shows that any model of set theory in first-order logic, if it is consistent, has an equivalent model which is countable. This appears contradictory, because Georg Cantor proved that there exist sets which are not countable. Thus the seeming contradiction is that a model that is itself countable, and which therefore contains only countable sets, satisfies the first-order sentence that intuitively states "there are uncountable sets".[48]
A mathematical explanation of the paradox, showing that it is not a true contradiction in mathematics, was first given in 1922 by Thoralf Skolem. He explained that the countability of a set is not absolute, but relative to the model in which the cardinality is measured. Skolem's work was harshly received by Ernst Zermelo, who argued against the limitations of first-order logic and Skolem's notion of "relativity", but the result quickly came to be accepted by the mathematical community.[49][48]
Real paradoxes
Cantor's paradox
Cantor's theorem state's that, for any set possibly infinite, its powerset has a strictly greater cardinality. For example, this means there is no bijection from to Cantor's paradox is a paradox in naive set theory, which shows that there cannot exist a "set of all sets" or "universe set". It starts by assuming there is some set of all sets, then it must be that is strictly smaller than thus But since contains all sets, we must have that and thus Therefore contradicting Cantor's theorem. This was one of the original paradoxes that added to the need for a formalized set theory to avoid these paradoxes. This paradox is usually resolved in formal set theories by disallowing unrestricted comprehension and the existence of a universe set.
Set of all cardinal numbers
Similar to Cantor's paradox, the paradox of the set of all cardinal numbers is a result due to unrestricted comprehension. It often uses the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinal numbers for representatives. It is related to the Burali-Forti paradox. It begins by assuming there is some set Then, if there is some largest element then the powerset is strictly greater, and thus not in Conversly, if there is no largest element, then the union contains the elements of all elements of and is therefore greater than or equal to each element. Since there is no largest element in for any element there is another element such that and Thus, for any and so
See also
- Cardinal function
- Inaccessible cardinal
- Infinitary combinatorics
- Large cardinal
- Numerosity (mathematics)
- Regular cardinal
- Scott's trick
- The Higher Infinite
- Von Neumann universe
- Zero sharp
References
Notes
- ^ The common definition of an equvalence relation supposes that the elements to be compared belong to a set. Since there is no set of all sets, for talking of equinumerosity as an equivalence relation, one needs to change the definition of an equivalence relation by allowing proper classes.
Citations
- ^ "Cardinality | Brilliant Math & Science Wiki". brilliant.org. Retrieved 2020-08-23.
- ^ Georg Cantor (1891). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 1: 75–78. English translation: Ewald, William B., ed. (1996). From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, Volume 2. Oxford University Press. pp. 920–922. ISBN 0-19-850536-1.
- ^ Bloch, Ethan D. (2011). Proofs and Fundamentals. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. Springer Science+Business Media. pp. 242–243. doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-7127-2. ISBN 978-1-4419-7126-5. ISSN 0172-6056. Archived from the original on 2022-01-22.
- ^ Ashlock, Daniel; Lee, Colin (2020). An Introduction to Proofs with Set Theory. Synthesis Lectures on Mathematics & Statistics. Springer Cham. pp. 181–182. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-02426-9. ISBN 978-3-031-01298-3. ISSN 1938-1743.
- ^ Cohen, Paul J. (December 15, 1963). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 50 (6): 1143–1148. Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C. doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143. JSTOR 71858. PMC 221287. PMID 16578557.
- ^ Cohen, Paul J. (January 15, 1964). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 51 (1): 105–110. Bibcode:1964PNAS...51..105C. doi:10.1073/pnas.51.1.105. JSTOR 72252. PMC 300611. PMID 16591132.
- ^ Penrose, R (2005), The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe, Vintage Books, ISBN 0-09-944068-7
- ^ Oxford English Dictionary, "cardinal (adj.), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/1490074521.
- ^ Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinal," Etymonline, Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinal.
- ^ Oxford English Dictionary, "cardinal number (n.), sense 1," July 2023, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/3193437451.
- ^ Oxford English Dictionary, "ordinal (n.2)," June 2024, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/6032173309.
- ^ Woodin, Greg; Winter, Bodo (2024). "Numbers in Context: Cardinals, Ordinals, and Nominals in American English". Cognitive Science. 48 (6) e13471. doi:10.1111/cogs.13471. PMC 11475258. PMID 38895756.
- ^ a b Ferreirós, José (2007). Labyrinth of Thought (2nd ed.). Basel: Birkhäuser. p. 24. doi:10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3. ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7.
- ^ a b Cantor, Georg (1932). Zermelo, Ernst (ed.). "Gesammelte Abhandlungen". Springer. Berlin: 151. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2. ISBN 978-3-662-00254-4.
{{cite journal}}
: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help) - ^ a b Steiner, Jacob (1867). Vorlesungen über synthetische Geometrie / 1 Die Theorie der Kegelschnitte in elementarer Form. Ghent University. Leipzig : Teubner.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: publisher location (link) - ^ Harper Douglas, "Etymology of cardinality," Etymonline, Online Etymology Dictionary, accessed April 20, 2025, https://www.etymonline.com/word/cardinality.
- ^ Oxford English Dictionary, "cardinality (n.2), Etymology," March 2025, https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/5444748676.
- ^ Cepelewicz, Jordana Animals Count and Use Zero. How Far Does Their Number Sense Go?, Quanta, August 9, 2021
- ^ "Early Human Counting Tools". Math Timeline. Retrieved 2018-04-26.
- ^ Duncan J. Melville (2003). Third Millennium Chronology Archived 2018-07-07 at the Wayback Machine, Third Millennium Mathematics. St. Lawrence University.
- ^ a b c Allen, Donald (2003). "The History of Infinity" (PDF). Texas A&M Mathematics. Archived from the original (PDF) on August 1, 2020. Retrieved Nov 15, 2019.
- ^ Allen, Reginald E. (1998). Plato's Parmenides. The Dialogues of Plato. Vol. 4. New Haven: Yale University Press. p. 256. ISBN 9780300138030. OCLC 47008500.
- ^ Klein, Jacob (1992) [1934]. Greek Mathematical Thought And The Origin Of Algebra. Translated by Brann, Eva. New York: Dover Publications. p. 46. ISBN 0-486-27289-3. LCCN 92-20992.
- ^ Mayberry, John P. (2011). Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-17271-4. ISSN 0953-4806.
- ^ Joseph, George Gheverghese (Oct 24, 2010). The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics (3rd ed.). Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. pp. 349–351. ISBN 978-0-691-13526-7. Archived from the original on 2024-08-05.
- ^ O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F. (2000). "MacTutor – Jaina mathematics". MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. Retrieved 2025-06-09 – via University of St Andrews, Scotland.
- ^ Drabkin, Israel E. (1950). "Aristotle's Wheel: Notes on the History of a Paradox". Osiris. 9: 162–198. doi:10.1086/368528. JSTOR 301848. S2CID 144387607.
- ^ Galilei, Galileo (1914) [1638]. Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences (PDF). Translated by Crew, Henry; De Salvio, Alfonso. New York: The Macmillan Company. pp. 31–33.
- ^ Ferreirós, José (2024), "The Early Development of Set Theory", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, archived from the original on 2021-05-12, retrieved 2025-01-04
- ^ Bolzano, Bernard (1975), Berg, Jan (ed.), Einleitung zur Größenlehre und erste Begriffe der allgemeinen Größenlehre, Bernard-Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe, edited by Eduard Winter et al., vol. II, A, 7, Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann Verlag, p. 152, ISBN 3-7728-0466-7
- ^ Bolzano, Bernard (1950). Paradoxes Of The Infinite. Translated by Prihonsky, Fr. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- ^ Hume, David (1739–1740). "Part III. Of Knowledge and Probability: Sect. I. Of Knowledge". A Treatise of Human Nature – via Project Gutenberg.
- ^ Frege, Gottlob (1884). "IV. Der Begriff der Anzahl § 63. Die Möglichkeit der eindeutigen Zuordnung als solches. Logisches Bedenken, dass die Gleichheit für diesen Fall besonders erklärt wird". Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik – via Project Gutenberg.
§63. Ein solches Mittel nennt schon Hume: »Wenn zwei Zahlen so combinirt werden, dass die eine immer eine Einheit hat, die jeder Einheit der andern entspricht, so geben wir sie als gleich an.«
- ^ Jeff Miller, Peter Flor, Gunnar Berg, and Julio González Cabillón. "Pigeonhole principle". In Jeff Miller (ed.) Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics. Electronic document, retrieved November 11, 2006
- ^ Rittaud, Benoît; Heeffer, Albrecht (2014). "The pigeonhole principle, two centuries before Dirichlet". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 36 (2): 27–29. doi:10.1007/s00283-013-9389-1. hdl:1854/LU-4115264. MR 3207654. S2CID 44193229.
- ^ Cantor, Herrn (1984) [1874], Cantor, Georg (ed.), "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen", Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfaltigkeiten: Arbeiten zur Mengenlehre aus den Jahren 1872–1884, Teubner-Archiv zur Mathematik (in German), vol. 2, Vienna: Springer, pp. 19–24, doi:10.1007/978-3-7091-9516-1_2, ISBN 978-3-7091-9516-1, retrieved 2025-05-24
- ^ Cantor, Georg (1890). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigketislehre". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 1: 72–78. ISSN 0012-0456.
- ^ Cantor, Georg (1895-11-01). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre". Mathematische Annalen (in German). 46 (4): 481–512. doi:10.1007/BF02124929. ISSN 1432-1807.
- ^ Cantor, Georg (1883-12-01). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten". Mathematische Annalen (in German). 21 (4): 545–591. doi:10.1007/BF01446819. ISSN 1432-1807.
- ^ Peano, G. (1890-03-01). "Sur une courbe, qui remplit toute une aire plane". Mathematische Annalen (in French). 36 (1): 157–160. doi:10.1007/BF01199438. ISSN 1432-1807. Archived from the original on 2018-07-22.
- ^ Gugenheimer, Heinrich Walter (1963), Differential Geometry, Courier Dover Publications, p. 3, ISBN 9780486157207
{{citation}}
: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help). - ^ Russell & Whitehead.
- ^ Russell, B. (1907). "On Some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types". Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. s2-4 (1): 29–53. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29. ISSN 1460-244X.
- ^ Gödel, Kurt (1938). "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 24 (12): 556–557. Bibcode:1938PNAS...24..556G. doi:10.1073/pnas.24.12.556. PMC 1077160. PMID 16577857.
- ^ Cohen, P. J. (1963). "THE INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 50 (6): 1143–1148. doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 221287. PMID 16578557.
- ^ Cohen, Paul Joseph (2008) [1966]. Set theory and the continuum hypothesis. Mineola, New York City: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-46921-8.
- ^ a b Gamov, George (1947). One two three... infinity. Viking Press. LCCN 62-24541. Archived on 2016-01-06
- ^ a b Bays, Timothy (2025), "Skolem's Paradox", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2025 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-04-13
- ^ van Dalen, Dirk; Ebbinghaus, Heinz-Dieter (Jun 2000). "Zermelo and the Skolem Paradox". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 6 (2): 145–161. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.137.3354. doi:10.2307/421203. hdl:1874/27769. JSTOR 421203. S2CID 8530810.
Bibliography
- Anellis, Irving M.; et al. (AMS-IMS-SIAM Joint Summer Research Conference) (1984). Axiomatic Set Theory. Contemporary Mathematics. Providence: American Mathematical Society. ISBN 0-8218-5026-1. LCCN 84-18457.
- Bourbaki, Nicholas (1968). Theory of Sets. Éléments de mathématique. Paris: Éditions Hermann. LCCN 68-25177.
- Enderton, Herbert (1977). Elements of Set Theory. New York: Academic Press. ISBN 0-12-238440-7. LCCN 76-27438.
- Ferreirós, José (2007). Labyrinth of Thought. Science Networks - Historical Studies (2nd ed.). Basel: Birkhäuser. doi:10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3. ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7. LCCN 2007931860. Archived from the original on 2019-07-09.
- Halmos, Paul R. (1998) [1974]. Naive Set Theory. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. New York: Springer Science+Business Media. doi:10.1007/978-1-4757-1645-0. ISBN 978-0-387-90092-6. ISSN 0172-6056. Archived from the original on 2023-01-12.
- Hrbáček, Karel; Jech, Thomas (2017) [1999]. Introduction to Set Theory (3rd, Revised and Expanded ed.). New York: CRC Press. doi:10.1201/9781315274096. ISBN 978-0-82477915-3. LCCN 99-15458.
- Kleene, Stephen Cole (1967). Mathematical Logic. New York: John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-49033-4. LCCN 66-26747.
- Krivine, Jean-Louis (1971). Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory. Synthese Library. New York: D. Reidel Publishing Company. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3144-8. ISBN 9780391001794. ISSN 0166-6991. LCCN 71-146965. Archived from the original on 2014-08-06.
- Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1968). Set Theory. Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing. LCCN 67-21972.
- Lévy, Azriel (1979). Basic Set Theory. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-08417-7. LCCN 78-1917.
- Russell, Bertrand; Whitehead, Alfred North (1973) [1927]. Principia Mathematica (PDF). Vol. II (2nd ed.). London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-06791-X.
- Stoll, Robert R. (1963). Set Theory and Logic. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman. ISBN 7167 0416-1. LCCN 63-8995.
{{cite book}}
: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help) - Suppes, Patrick (1972) [1960]. Axiomatic Set Theory. Dover Books on Mathematics. New York: Dover. ISBN 0-486-61630-4. LCCN 72-86226. Archived from the original on 2014-08-06.
- Takeuti, Gaisi; Zaring, Wilson M (1982). Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory. Graduate Texts in Mathematics (2nd ed.). New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-8168-6. ISBN 0-387-90683-5. ISSN 0072-5285. LCCN 81-8838. Archived from the original on 2014-08-06.
- Tao, Terence (2022). Analysis I. Texts and Readings in Mathematics (4th ed.). Singapore: Springer Science+Business Media. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2. ISBN 978-981-19-7261-4. ISSN 2366-8717.