History of philosophy: Difference between revisions
Appearance
Content deleted Content added
WikiJunkie (talk | contribs) ←Removed redirect to Philosophy#Historical overview Tag: Removed redirect |
Undid revision 888989303 by WikiJunkie (talk)why? |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
#REDIRECT [[Philosophy#Historical_overview]] |
|||
{{Other uses|History of Philosophy (disambiguation)}} |
|||
{{Philosophy sidebar}} |
|||
{{Redirect category shell|1= |
|||
The '''history of philosophy''' consists of the compilation and study of philosophical ideas and concepts through time. Issues specifically related to history of philosophy might include (but are not limited to): How can changes in philosophy be accounted for historically? What drives the development of thought in its historical context? To what degree can philosophical texts from prior historical eras be understood even today? |
|||
{{R from merge}} |
|||
{{R to section}} |
|||
All cultures — be they [[prehistoric]], [[medieval]], or [[Modernism|modern]]; [[Eastern hemisphere|Eastern]], [[Western hemisphere|Western]], [[religious]] or [[secular]] — have had their own unique schools of philosophy, arrived at through both inheritance and through independent discovery. Such theories have grown from different [[premise]]s and approaches, examples of which include (but are not limited to) [[rationalism]] (theories arrived at through pure reason), [[empiricism]] (theories arrived at through observation), and even through [[leap of faith|leaps of faith]], hope and inheritance (such as the [[supernatural]]ist philosophies and [[religion]]s). |
|||
History of philosophy seeks to catalogue and classify such development. The goal is to understand the development of philosophical ideas through time. |
|||
== Western philosophy == |
|||
{{redirect|History of Western Philosophy|the book by Bertrand Russell|A History of Western Philosophy}} |
|||
[[Western philosophy]] has a long history, conventionally divided into four large eras - the Ancient, Medieval, Modern, and Contemporary. The Ancient era runs through the fall of Rome and includes the Greek philosophers such as [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]]. The Medieval period runs until roughly the late 15th century and the [[Renaissance]]. The "Modern" is a word with more varied use, which includes everything from Post-Medieval through the specific period up to the 20th century. Contemporary philosophy encompasses the philosophical developments of the 20th century up to the present day. |
|||
===Ancient philosophy=== |
|||
{{Further|Ancient philosophy}} |
|||
====Pre-Socratics==== |
|||
[[File:Turkey ancient region map ionia.JPG|thumb|right|200px|[[Ionia]], source of early Greek philosophy, in western [[Asia Minor]]]] |
|||
Western Philosophy is generally said to begin in the Greek cities of western Asia Minor (Ionia) with [[Thales]] of [[Miletus]], who was active around 585 B.C. and left us the opaque dictum, "all is water." His most noted students were respectively [[Anaximander]] (all is [[Apeiron (cosmology)|apeiron]] (roughly, ''the unlimited'')) and [[Anaximenes of Miletus]] ("all is air"). |
|||
[[Pythagoras]], from the island of Samos off the coast of Ionia, later lived at Croton in southern Italy (Magna Graecia). [[Pythagoreanism|Pythagorean]]s hold that "all is number," giving ''formal'' accounts in contrast to the previous ''material'' of the Ionians. They also believe in [[metempsychosis]], the transmigration of souls, or reincarnation. |
|||
[[File:Zeno Achilles Paradox.png|thumb|left|140px|Zeno's Paradox, ''Achilles and the Tortoise'']] |
|||
=====Being and becoming===== |
|||
The first true philosophic dialectic occurs between the "[[Becoming (philosophy)|becoming]]" of [[Heraclitus]] ("all is fire", "everything flows," all is chaotic and transitory) of Ephesus in Ionia and the "[[being]]" of [[Parmenides]] (all is One, change is impossible) of [[Eleatic School|Elea]] in Magna Graecia. His student [[Zeno of Elea|Zeno]] argued against motion with [[Zeno's paradoxes|his famous paradoxes]]. Heraclitus also introduced the concept of ''[[logos]]''. |
|||
=====Pluralism===== |
|||
Other thinkers and schools appeared throughout Greece over the next few centuries. Among the most important was the [[Pluralism (philosophy)|pluralism]] of [[Anaxagoras]]. In response to Parmenides on the impossibility of change, Anaxagoras described the world as a mixture of primary imperishable ingredients, where material variation was never caused by an absolute presence of a particular ingredient, but rather by its relative preponderance over the other ingredients; in his words, "each one is... most manifestly those things of which there are the most in it".<ref name=Curd>{{cite book|author=Anaxagoras|editor1-last=Curd|editor1-first=Patricia|title=A Presocratics Reader|publisher=Hackett|isbn=978-1-60384-305-8|chapter=Anaxagoras of Clazomenae|quote=B12}}</ref> He introduced the concept of ''[[Nous]]'' (Mind) as an ordering force, which moved and separated out the original mixture, which was [[homogeneous]], or nearly so. |
|||
[[File:Four elements representation.svg|thumb|150px|The Four Elements]] |
|||
[[Empedocles]] also proposed powers called Love and Hate which would act as forces to bring about the mixture and separation of the elements, more discreet than in the mixture of Anaxagoras. Empedocles' philosophy is best known for being the originator of the [[Cosmogony|cosmogenic]] theory of the four [[Classical elements]]. Empedocles is generally considered the last Greek philosopher to record his ideas in verse. Some of his work survives, more than in the case of any other Presocratic philosopher. |
|||
[[File:Cornelis Cornelisz. van Haarlem 01.jpg|thumb|220px|left|Democritus (laughing) & Herakleitos (crying) by [[Cornelis van Haarlem|van Haarlem]]]] |
|||
=====Atomism and Sophistry===== |
|||
There were also the [[Sophistry|Sophists]], who became known, perhaps unjustly, for claiming that truth was no more than opinion and for teaching people to argue fallaciously to prove whatever conclusions they wished. Most famous them of was [[Protagoras]] who left us the dictum "man is the measure of all things." Another school was the [[atomism|atomists]] such as [[Leucippus]] and [[Democritus]], wherein the world is a composite of innumerable interacting parts. |
|||
====Athens==== |
|||
This whole philosophical movement gradually became more concentrated in [[History of Athens|Athens]], which had become the dominant city-state in [[Greece]]. |
|||
There is considerable discussion about why Athenian culture encouraged philosophy. It is known from Plato's writings that many sophists maintained schools of debate, were respected members of society, and were well paid by their students. Orators influenced Athenian history, possibly even causing its failure (See [[Battle of Lade]]). Another theory explains the birth of philosophical debate in Athens with the presence of a slave labor workforce which performed the necessary functions that would otherwise have consumed the time of the free male citizenry. Freed from working in the fields or other manual economic activities, they were able to participate in the assemblies of Athens and spend long periods in discussions on popular philosophical questions. Students of Sophists needed to acquire the skills of oration in order to influence the Athenian Assembly and thereby increase respect and wealth. In response, the subjects and methods of debate became highly developed by the Sophists. |
|||
=====Socrates===== |
|||
[[File:Socrates Pio-Clementino Inv314.jpg|thumb|180px|Bust of Socrates]] |
|||
The key figure in transforming Greek philosophy into a unified and continuous project - one still being pursued today - is [[Socrates]], who studied under several Sophists. It is said that following a visit to the [[Oracle of Delphi]] he spent much of his life questioning anyone in Athens who would engage him, in order to disprove the oracular prophecy that there would be no man wiser than Socrates. Through these live dialogues, he examined common but critical concepts that lacked clear or concrete definitions, such as beauty and truth, and the virtues of piety, wisdom, temperance, courage, and justice. Socrates' awareness of his own ignorance allowed him to discover his errors as well as the errors of those who claimed knowledge based upon falsifiable or unclear precepts and beliefs. He wrote nothing, but inspired many disciples, including many sons of prominent Athenian citizens (including [[Plato]]), which led to his [[Socrates#Trial and death|trial and execution]] in 399 B.C. on the charge that his philosophy and sophistry were undermining the youth, [[piety]], and moral fiber of the city. He was offered a chance to flee from his fate but chose to remain in Athens, abide by his principles, and drink the poison [[Conium|hemlock]]. |
|||
[[File:Plato - Allegory of the Cave.png|thumb|200px|left|Plato's Allegory of the Cave]] |
|||
=====Plato===== |
|||
Socrates' most important student was Plato, who founded the [[Academy]] of Athens and wrote a number of dialogues, which applied the [[Socratic method]] of inquiry to examine philosophical problems. Some central ideas of Plato's dialogues are the [[The Forms|Theory of Forms]], i.e., that the mind is imbued with an innate capacity to understand and contemplate concepts from a higher order preeminent world, concepts more real, permanent, and universal than or representative of the ''things of this world'', which are only changing and temporal; the idea of the immortal soul being superior to the body; the idea of evil as simple ignorance of truth; that true knowledge leads to true virtue; that art is subordinate to moral purpose; and that the society of the [[city-state]] should be governed by a merit class of propertyless philosopher kings, with no permanent wives or paternity rights over their children, and be protected by an athletically gifted, honorable, duty bound military class. In the later dialogues Socrates figures less prominently, but Plato had previously woven his own thoughts into some of Socrates' words. Interestingly, in his most famous work, ''[[Plato's Republic|The Republic]]'', Plato critiques democracy, condemns tyranny, and proposes a three tiered merit based structure of society, with workers, guardians and philosophers, in an equal relationship, where no innocents would ever be put to death again, citing the philosophers' relentless love of truth and knowledge of the forms or ideals, concern for general welfare and lack of propertied interest as causes for their being suited to govern. |
|||
=====Aristotle===== |
|||
Plato's most outstanding student was [[Aristotle]], perhaps the first truly systematic philosopher. [[Aristotelian logic]] was the first type of [[logic]] to attempt to categorize every valid [[syllogism]]. A syllogism is a form of argument that is guaranteed to be accepted, because it is known (by all educated persons) to be [[validity|valid]]. A crucial assumption in [[Aristotelian logic]] is that it has to be about real objects. Two of Aristotle's syllogisms are invalid to modern eyes. For example, "All A are B. All A are C. Therefore, some B are C." This syllogism fails if set A is empty, but there are real members of set B. In Aristotle's syllogistic logic you could say this, because his logic should only be used for things that really exist ("no empty classes"). |
|||
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|180px|Plato ''(left)'' and Aristotle ''(right)'']] |
|||
The application of [[Aristotelian logic]] is preceded by having the student memorize a rather large set of syllogisms. The memorization proceeded from diagrams, or learning a key sentence, with the first letter of each word reminding the student of the names of the syllogisms. Each syllogism had a name, for example: ''[[modus ponens]]'' had the form of "If A is true, then B is true. A is true, therefore B is true." Most university students of logic memorized Aristotle's 19 syllogisms of two subjects, permitting them to validly connect a subject and object. A few logicians developed systems with three subjects, or described a way of elaborating the rules of three subjects. |
|||
======Hellenistic====== |
|||
Other pupils of Socrates aside from Plato founded their own schools, such as [[Euclid of Megara]]. The Hellenistic period involves the [[Cyrenaics]] of [[Aristippus]] and [[Cynicism (philosophy)|Cynics]] of [[Antisthenes]] resolving themselves in the [[Epicurean]] and [[Stoicism|Stoic]] schools. Skepticism also belongs to this period. |
|||
=== Medieval philosophy === |
|||
{{Further|Medieval philosophy}} |
|||
The history of western medieval philosophy is generally divided into two periods, early medieval philosophy, which started with [[St. Augustine]] in the mid 4th century and lasted until the recovery in the 13th century West of a great bulk of [[Aristotle]]'s works and their subsequent translation into Latin from the Arabic and Greek, and high medieval philosophy, which came about as a result of the recovery of Aristotle. This period, which lasted a mere century and a half compared to the nine centuries of the early period, came to a close around the time of [[William of Ockham]] in the middle of the 14th century. Western medieval philosophy was primarily concerned with implementing the Christian faith with philosophical reason, that is, "baptizing" reason. |
|||
Early medieval philosophy was influenced by the likes of [[Stoicism]], [[neo-Platonism]], but, above all, the philosophy of [[Plato]] himself. The prominent figure of this period was St. Augustine who adopted Plato's thought and Christianized it in the 4th century and whose influence dominated medieval philosophy perhaps up to end of the era but was checked with the arrival of Aristotle's texts. Augustinianism was the preferred starting point for most philosophers (including the great [[St. Anselm of Canterbury]]) up until the 13th century. |
|||
During the later years of the early medieval period and throughout the years of the high medieval period, there was a great emphasis on the nature of God and the application of [[Aristotle]]'s [[term logic|logic]] and thought to every area of life. Attempts were made to reconcile these three things by means of [[scholasticism]]. One continuing interest in this time was to prove the existence of God, through logic alone, if possible. The point of this exercise was not so much to justify belief in God, since in the view of medieval Christianity this was self-evident, but to make classical philosophy, with its extra-biblical pagan origins, respectable in a Christian context. |
|||
[[File:Carlo Crivelli 007.jpg|thumb|140px|Thomas Aquinas]] |
|||
One monumental effort to overcome mere logical argument at the beginning of the high medieval period was to follow Aristotelian demonstration by starting from effects and reasoning up to their causes. This took the form of the [[cosmological argument]], conventionally attributed to [[St. Thomas Aquinas]]. The argument roughly is that everything that exists has a cause. But since there could not be an infinite chain of causes back into the past, there must have been an uncaused "first cause." This is God. Aquinas also adapted this argument to prove the goodness of God. Everything has some goodness, and the cause of each thing is better than the thing caused. Therefore, the first cause is the best possible thing. Similar arguments were used to prove God's power and uniqueness. |
|||
Another important argument for proof of the existence of God was the [[ontological argument]], advanced by [[St. Anselm]]. Basically, it says that God is that than which nothing greater can be thought. There is nothing that simply exists in the mind that can be said to be greater than something that enjoys existence in reality. Hence the greatest thing that the mind can conceive of must exist in reality. Therefore, God exists. This argument has been used in different forms by philosophers from Descartes forward. |
|||
In addition to St. Thomas Aquinas, St. Augustine and St. Anselm, other important names from the medieval period include [[Blessed John Duns Scotus]], [[St. Bonaventure]], [[Anicius Manlius Severinus Boëthius]], and [[Pierre Abélard]]. |
|||
The definition of the word "philosophy" in English has changed over the centuries. In medieval times, any research outside the fields of [[theology]] or [[medicine]] was called "philosophy", hence the [[Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society]] is a scientific journal dating from 1665, the [[Doctor of Philosophy]] (Ph.D.) degree covers a wide range of subjects, and the [[Cambridge Philosophical Society]] is actually concerned with what we would now call [[science]] and not modern philosophy. |
|||
=== Renaissance philosophy === |
|||
{{multiple issues|section=yes|{{unreferenced section|date=July 2014}} |
|||
{{POV-section|date=July 2014}} |
|||
}} |
}} |
||
{{Main|Renaissance philosophy}} |
|||
Contemporary philosophical historiography emphasizes a great "gap" between Middle Ages and Modern thought. And often this "gap" is used as a mean to characterize the meaning of the word "modern" used in "modern philosophy". As a matter of fact, if in History Middle Ages are said to end symbolically with the Columbus' voyages (1492), periodisation in Philosophy is not necessarily reducible to the broader one. |
|||
Between the development of High Scholasticism (13th and part of the 14th centuries) and the empiricists-rationalists disputes charactering modern philosophy (starting in the 17th century) several thinkers developed transitional systems of thought. One main focus was on emancipating from the supremacy of theology on the other branches of the humanities, including aesthetics, rhetorics and the beginning of natural observations. |
|||
Along with the figurative arts, music, vernacular languages and literatures, and the Christian religion, philosophy was greatly renewed in what is usually referred to as the [[Renaissance]]. This cultural movement, spreading throughout Europe from Italy, influenced philosophy as much as architecture, the visual arts, and literature. |
|||
Two circumstancial events promoted an emancipation of philosophy from the Catholic theology (which had dominated European thought throughout the Middle Ages): the concurrent Protestant Reformation, and the use of vernacular languages (Italian, English, French) instead of Latin in treatises and public discussions. |
|||
If most medieval philosophers were priests and monks, early and late Renaissance philosophers were a more heterogeneous population, including rhetors, magicians and astrologues, early empirical scientists, poets, and philologists. If there was one common theme among these Renaissance thinkers it would have to be a concern for humanity (and the humanities) and the search for human specificity. The study of ''humanae litterae'' overcame that of ''divinae litterae'', and opened the way for modern skepticism and science. |
|||
[[File:Santi di Tito - Niccolo Machiavelli's portrait.jpg|thumb|Santi di Tito - Niccolò Machiavelli's portrait]] |
|||
Many philosophers from the Renaissance are today read and remembered, even though often they are not often categorized into a single category. In particular, those Renaissance thinkers who were especially oriented towards empiricism and rationalism, are often seen as early ([[Galileo Galilei]]) or very early ([[Machiavelli]]) modern philosophers. On the other hand, those heavily influenced by esoteric traditions (like [[Giovanni Pico della Mirandola]], [[Marsilio Ficino]] and even [[Nicholas of Cusa]] and [[Giordano Bruno]]) are often seen as (very) late Medieval philosophers. This categorisation may however seem to interpret two centuries of philosophy on the basis of a contemporary discrimination ("esoteric"/"scientific"). A few thinkers who do not clearly fall into either of these categories are usually fully recognized as Renaissance philosophers, including [[Montaigne]], [[Tommaso Campanella]], [[Telesius]], [[Erasmus]], and [[Thomas More]]. |
|||
=== Modern philosophy === |
|||
{{Main|Modern philosophy}} |
|||
{{Further|17th-century philosophy|18th-century philosophy|19th-century philosophy}} |
|||
[[File:Frans Hals - Portret van René Descartes.jpg|thumb|140px|René Descartes]] |
|||
As with many periodizations, there are multiple current usages for the term "Modern Philosophy" that exist in practice. One - common - usage is to date modern philosophy from the "[[Age of Reason]]", where systematic philosophy became common, excluding Erasmus and Machiavelli (writing in the 15th century) as "modern philosophers", and traditionally considering [[Hobbes]] (writing in the 17th century) as the first truly "modern" philosopher. The grounding of philosophy in problems of ''knowledge'', rather than problems of metaphysics, dominates the era, exemplified most perhaps in the philosophy of [[René Descartes]].<ref name=diane>{{cite book|page=125|title=Fifty Major Philosophers, A Reference Guide|author=Diane Collinson}}</ref> |
|||
[[File:Immanuel Kant (painted_portrait).jpg|thumb|left|150px|Immanuel Kant]] |
|||
Another is to date it, the way the entire larger modern period is dated, from the Renaissance. There is also the [[lumpers/splitters]] problem, namely that some works split philosophy into more periods than others: one author might feel a strong need to differentiate between "The Age of Reason" or "Early Modern Philosophers" and "The Enlightenment"; another author might write from the perspective that 1600-1800 is essentially one continuous evolution, and therefore a single period. Wikipedia's philosophy section therefore hews more closely to centuries as a means of avoiding long discussions over periods, but it is important to note the variety of practice that occurs. |
|||
[[17th-century philosophy]] is dominated by the need to organize philosophy on rational, skeptical, logical and axiomatic grounds, such as the work of Descartes, [[Blaise Pascal]], and [[Thomas Hobbes]]. This type of philosophy attempts to integrate religious belief into philosophical frameworks, and, often to combat atheism or other skeptical beliefs, by adopting the idea of material reality, and the [[dualism]] between spirit and material. The extension, and reaction, against this would be the monism of [[George Berkeley]] ([[Idealism#George Berkeley|idealism]]) and [[Benedict de Spinoza]] ([[Double-aspect theory|dual aspect theory]]). It was during this time period that the empiricism was developed as an alternative to skepticism by [[John Locke]], [[George Berkeley]] and others. It should be mentioned that [[John Locke]] and [[Thomas Hobbes]] developed their well known political philosophies during this time, as well. |
|||
[[File:Painting of David Hume.jpg|thumb|upright|[[David Hume]]]] |
|||
The [[18th-century philosophy]] article deals with the period often called the early part of "The Enlightenment" in the shorter form of the word, and centers on the rise of systematic empiricism, following after [[Sir Isaac Newton]]'s natural philosophy. Thus the ''philosophes'' like [[Diderot]], [[Voltaire]], [[Rousseau]], and [[Montesquieu]] and the political philosophies embodied by and influencing the [[American Revolution]] and [[American Enlightenment]], such as [[Cesare Beccaria|Beccaria]], are part of [[The Enlightenment]]. [[Immanuel Kant]] perhaps is most prominent in the period, seeking a large, systematic reconciliation of rationalism and empiricism with claim that the mind structured experience. Kant took himself to have anointed a [[Copernican Revolution]] in philosophy. |
|||
Other prominent philosophers of this time period were [[David Hume]] and [[Adam Smith]], who, along with [[Francis Hutcheson (philosopher)|Francis Hutcheson]] and [[Thomas Reid]], were the primary philosophers of the [[Scottish Enlightenment]]; and [[Thomas Paine]] and [[Thomas Jefferson]], who were philosophers of the [[American Enlightenment]]. [[Edmund Burke]] was influenced by the Scottish Enlightenment, namely Hume's skepticism and reliance on tradition and the passions, and while supporting the American Revolution based on the established rights of Englishmen, rejected the "natural rights" claims of the Enlightenment and vehemently rejected the Rationalism of the French Revolution (see [[Reflections on the Revolution in France]]). |
|||
The [[19th-century philosophy|19th century]] took the radical notions of self-organization and intrinsic order from Goethe and Kantian metaphysics, and proceeded to produce a long elaboration on the tension between systematization and organic development. Foremost was the work of [[Hegel]], whose ''Logic'' and ''Phenomenology of Spirit'' produced a "dialectical" framework for ordering of knowledge. The 19th century would also include [[Arthur Schopenhauer|Schopenhauer]]'s affirmation of the will, drawing parallels to Eastern philosophy. Schopenhauer profoundly influenced [[Friedrich Nietzsche]]. |
|||
[[File:G.W.F. Hegel (by Sichling, after Sebbers).jpg|thumb|left|140px|Hegel]] |
|||
Also in the 19th century, the Danish philosopher [[Søren Kierkegaard]] took philosophy in a new direction by focusing less on abstract concepts and more on what it means to be an ''existing'' individual. His work provided impetus for many 20th century philosophical movements, including [[existentialism]]. As with the 18th century, it would be developments in science that would arise from, and then challenge, philosophy: most importantly the work of Charles Darwin, which was based on the idea of organic self-regulation found in philosophers such as Smith, but fundamentally challenged established conceptions. |
|||
=== Contemporary philosophy === |
|||
{{Further|Contemporary philosophy}} |
|||
The [[20th-century philosophy|20th century]] deals with the upheavals produced by a series of conflicts within philosophical discourse over the basis of knowledge, with classical certainties overthrown, and new social, economic, scientific and logical problems. 20th century philosophy was set for a series of attempts to reform and preserve, and to alter or abolish, older knowledge systems. Seminal figures include [[Gottlob Frege]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[Martin Heidegger]], [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], and [[Edmund Husserl]]. Since the Second World War, contemporary philosophy has been divided mostly into [[Analytic philosophy|analytic]] and [[Continental philosophy|continental]] traditions; the former carried in the English speaking world and the latter on the continent of Europe. The perceived conflict between continental and analytic schools of philosophy remains prominent, despite increasing skepticism regarding the distinction's usefulness. Knowledge and its basis has been a central concern, as seen from the work of Heidegger, Russell, [[G. E. Moore]], [[Karl Popper]], and [[Claude Lévi-Strauss]]. |
|||
The philosophy of the present century is difficult to clarify due to its immaturity. A number of surviving 20th century philosophers have established themselves as early voices of influence in the 21st. These include [[Noam Chomsky]], [[Saul Kripke]], and [[Jürgen Habermas]]. A variety of new topics have risen to the stage in analytic philosophy, orienting much of contemporary discourse in the field of [[ethics]]. New inquiries consider, for example, the ethical implications of new media and information exchange. Such developments have rekindled interest in the [[philosophy of technology]] and [[philosophy of science|science]]. There has been increased enthusiasm for highly specialized areas in philosophy of science, such as in the [[Bayesian probability|Bayesian]] school of [[epistemology]]. |
|||
====Analytic==== |
|||
[[File:Young frege.jpg|thumb|150px|Gottlob Frege]] |
|||
Arguably the biggest development was Frege's grounding of philosophy in logic rather than knowledge, a radical change from philosophy since Descartes.<ref name=diane/> Frege also helped with the likes of [[George Boole]] to overturn Aristotle's logic which had held sway for millennia. |
|||
=====Logicism===== |
|||
The [[Logicist]] project to ground mathematics in logic dominates the era, receiving a serious setback from [[Russell's Paradox]], and perhaps defeated utterly by [[Godel's Incompleteness Theorem]]. . |
|||
[[File:Russell in 1938.jpg|thumb|left|140px|Bertrand Russell]] |
|||
Russell, during his early career, along with his collaborator [[Alfred North Whitehead]], much influenced by Frege, who developed [[predicate logic]], which allowed a much greater range of sentences to be parsed into logical form than was possible using the ancient Aristotelian logic. |
|||
Like Frege, Russell attempted to show that mathematics is reducible to logical fundamentals in [[The Principles of Mathematics]] (1903). Later, his book written with Whitehead, ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (1910–13), encouraged many philosophers to renew their interest with the development of [[Mathematical logic|symbolic logic]]. Additionally, Russell adopted Frege's predicate logic as his primary philosophical method, a method Russell thought could expose the underlying structure of philosophical problems. Russell sought to resolve various philosophical problems by applying such logical distinctions, most famously in his analysis of [[definite description]]s in "On Denoting."<ref>{{cite journal |last=Russell|first=Bertrand|year=1905|title=On Denoting|journal= [[Mind (journal)|Mind]]|volume=14|pages=473–93|url=http://www.fh-augsburg.de/~harsch/anglica/Chronology/20thC/Russell/rus_deno.html}}</ref> |
|||
The period is marked by the [[logical holism]] of Moore, Russell, early Wittgenstein, and [[Rudolf Carnap]] Inspired by developments of modern logic, the early Russell claimed that the problems of philosophy can be solved by showing the simple constituents of complex notions.<ref name="PenguinDicP22"/> An important aspect of British idealism was logical holism—the opinion that the aspects of the world cannot be known wholly without also knowing the whole world. This is closely related to the opinion that [[Property (philosophy)#Relations|relations]] between items are actually ''internal relations'', that is, [[Property (philosophy)|properties]] internal to the nature of those items. Russell, along with Wittgenstein, in response promulgated [[logical atomism]] and the doctrine of ''external relations''—- the belief that the world consists of ''independent'' facts.<ref>Baillie, James, "Introduction to Bertrand Russell" in ''Contemporary Analytic Philosophy, Second Edition'' (Prentice Hall, 1997), p. 25.</ref> |
|||
====="Psychologism"===== |
|||
Since its beginning, a basic principle of analytic philosophy has been conceptual clarity,<ref name="PenguinDicP22">Mautner, Thomas (editor) (2005) ''The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy'', entry for 'Analytic philosophy'', pp.22–3</ref> in the name of which Moore and Russell rejected [[Hegelianism]], which they accused of obscurity.<ref>See for example Moore's ''[[A Defence of Common Sense]]'' and Russell's critique of the [[Doctrine of internal relations]],</ref><ref>"Analytic philosophy opposed right from its beginning English neo-Hegelianism of Bradley's sort and similar ones. It did not only criticize the latter's denial of the existence of an external world (anyway an unjust criticism), but also the bombastic, obscure style of Hegel's writings." {{cite journal |last=Jonkers|first=Peter|year=2003|title=Perspectives on Twentieth Century Philosophy:A Reply to Tom Rockmore|journal=[[Ars Disputandi]]|volume=3|issn=1566-5399|url=http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000129/article.pdf}}</ref> |
|||
[[File:Ludwig Wittgenstein.jpg|thumb|140px|Ludwig Wittgenstein]] |
|||
In contrast to Husserl's 1891 book ''Philosophie der Arithmetik'', which attempted to show that the concept of the [[cardinal number]] derived from psychical acts of grouping objects and counting them,<ref>{{cite journal |author=Willard, Dallas|title=Husserl on a Logic that Failed|journal=Philosophical Review|pages=52–53|volume=89|issue=1|doi=10.2307/2184863}}</ref> Frege sought to show that mathematics and logic have their own validity, independent of the judgments or mental states of individual mathematicians and logicians (which were the basis of arithmetic according to the "[[psychologism]]" of Husserl's ''Philosophie''). Frege further developed his philosophy of logic and mathematics in ''[[The Foundations of Arithmetic]]'' and ''The Basic Laws of Arithmetic'' where he provided an alternative to psychological accounts of the concept of number. Husserl later gave devastating critiques of psychologism. |
|||
Late 19th-century English philosophy was dominated by [[British idealism]], as taught by philosophers like [[F. H. Bradley]] and [[Thomas Hill Green]]. It was with reference to this intellectual basis that the initiators of analytic philosophy, Moore and Russell, articulated early analytic philosophy. |
|||
=====Language===== |
|||
Though much alluded to in Frege, Wittgenstein saw all philosophical problems as problems of language. The early Wittgenstein and the [[logical positivists]] saw language as utterly reducible to logical terms, perhaps best exemplified in Russell's theory of definite descriptions. The later Wittgenstein, as well as the overthrow of the logical positivists by the likes of [[W. V. O. Quine]], has led others to see language as a social phenomenon on the whole not reducible to simplest terms. These latter thinkers have been pejoratively dubbed "[[lotus eaters]]". The strongest support of the latter is probably found in the theory of [[implicature]] and in [[J. L. Austin]]'s theory of [[performative utterance]]. |
|||
[[File:Wvq-passport-1975-400dpi-crop.jpg|thumb|left|130px|W. V. O. Quine]] |
|||
The issue of whether terms have meaning in virtue of the objects to which they refer has also led to much debate. Frege denied this, and much of Kripke's fame comes from disputing Frege on this. Kripke has made influential and original contributions to logic, especially [[modal logic]]. His work has profoundly influenced the analytic tradition, with his principal contribution being a semantics for modal logic, involving [[possible world]]s as described in a system now called [[Kripke semantics]].<ref>Jerry Fodor, "[http://www.lrb.co.uk/v26/n20/jerry-fodor/waters-water-everywhere Water's water everywhere]", ''London Review of Books'', 21 October 2004</ref> [[David Lewis (philosopher)|David Lewis]], a notable student of Quine, is probably best known for his controversial [[modal realism|modal realist]] stance that possible worlds exist; our world but one among them. That is, when you say "It is possible you could jump over the moon" an actual world exists wherein you are jumping over the moon. |
|||
====Continental==== |
|||
Phenomenologically oriented metaphysics undergirded [[existentialism]] (Heidegger, Sartre, [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], [[Albert Camus]]) and finally [[poststructuralism]] ([[Gilles Deleuze]], [[Jean-François Lyotard]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[Jacques Derrida]]). To show the general attitude of analytic philosophers to continental types, one can source Quine's claim that Derrida is a kind of "pseudophilosophy". [[Pragmatism|Pragmatist]] [[Richard Rorty]] has argued that these and other schools of 20th century philosophy, including his own, share an opposition to classical [[Dualism (philosophy of mind)|dualism]] that is both [[anti-essentialism|anti-essentialist]] and antimetaphysical.<ref>Rorty, Richard. ''Philosophy and Social Hope''. Penguin.1999: 47-48.</ref> The [[Psychoanalysis|psychoanalytic]] work of [[Sigmund Freud]], [[Jacques Lacan]], [[Julia Kristeva]], and others has also been influential in contemporary continental thought. Conversely, some philosophers have attempted to define and rehabilitate older traditions of philosophy. Most notably, [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] and [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] have both, albeit in different ways, revived the tradition of [[Aristotelianism]]. |
|||
In contemporary continental thought, a number of developments are taking place. The field of [[postcolonial theory]], championed in the late 20th century by theorists such as [[Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak]] and [[Homi K. Bhabha]] has established itself as a major academic presence. The Slovenian philosopher [[Slavoj Žižek]] remains tremendously popular in both academic and popular demographics, synthesizing [[Jacques Lacan|Lacanian]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegelian]], and [[Louis Althusser|Althusserian]] [[Marxism|Marxist]] thought in discussions of popular culture and politics. Žižek is also involved with the contemporary thrust to step beyond [[postmodernism]] and the [[linguistic turn]] of the 20th century. Key contributors to this movement are the French [[Alain Badiou]], and those classified under the blanket designation of [[speculative realism]], including [[Quentin Meillassoux]] and [[Ray Brassier]]. On the other hand, the American philosopher [[Judith Butler]] has strong support among many demographics in her close readings of [[speech act|language]], [[Gender Trouble|gender]], [[subjection|subjectivity]], [[materialism|corporeality]], [[Antigone|kinship]], [[war]] and non-violent [[Anti-zionism|ethics]]. As a result, she has received strong criticism from [[Žižek]], [[Martha Nussbaum]] and radical [[Zionists]]. |
|||
== Eastern philosophy == |
|||
{{Main|Eastern philosophy}} |
|||
In [[Western culture|the West]], the term [[Eastern philosophy]] refers very broadly to the various [[philosophy|philosophies]] of "the East", namely [[Asia]], including [[China]], [[India]], [[Japan]], [[Persian Empire|Persia]] and the general area. One must take into account that this term ignores that these countries do not belong to a single culture. Ancient eastern philosophy developed mainly in [[India]] and [[China]]. |
|||
===Babylonian philosophy=== |
|||
''See article [[Babylonian literature#Philosophy|Babylonian literature: Philosophy]]'' |
|||
=== Indian philosophy === |
|||
''See article [[Indian philosophy]] and [[Timeline of Eastern philosophers#Indian philosophers]] |
|||
''See also [[Hindu philosophy]], [[Buddhist philosophy]] and [[Jain Philosophy]]'' |
|||
Indian philosophy primarily begins with the later part of [[Rig Veda]], which was compiled before 1100 BCE.<ref>Oberlies (1998:155) gives an estimate of 1100 BC for the youngest hymns in book 10. Estimates for a ''terminus post quem'' of the earliest hymns are more uncertain. Oberlies (p. 158) based on 'cumulative evidence' sets wide range of 1700–1100</ref> Most of philosophy of the Rig Veda is contained in the sections [[Purusha sukta]] and [[Nasadiya Sukta]]. [[Vedas]] are followed by [[Upanishads]]; the oldest, such as the [[Brhadaranyaka]] and [[Chandogya]] Upanishads, have been dated to around the 8th century BCE. The philosophical edifice of Indian religions viz., [[Hinduism]], [[Jainism]], [[Buddhism]] is built on the foundation laid by the Upanishads. Upanishadic thoughts were followed by the Buddhist and Jain philosophies. |
|||
=== Persian philosophy === |
|||
''See article [[Iranian philosophy]]'' |
|||
''See also [[Zoroastrianism]]'' |
|||
=== Chinese philosophy === |
|||
''See article [[Chinese philosophy]] and [[Buddhist philosophy#Chinese Buddhism]]'' |
|||
[[Confucianism]] can be considered as the oldest school of philosophy in China.{{Citation needed|date=December 2009}} Confucianism developed in China around the same time as Buddhism and Jainism developed in India. Another school of philosophy, [[Taoism]], developed in China around 200 BC.{{Citation needed|date=December 2009}} |
|||
== Monotheistic philosophy == |
|||
{{See also|Abrahamic religions}} |
|||
Monotheistic philosophy, in its loosest sense, comprises the series of philosophical schools that emerged from the study and commentary of the common ancient [[Semitic people|Semitic]] tradition which can be traced by their adherents to [[Abraham]] ("Father/Leader of many" Hebrew אַבְרָהָם ("Avraham") Arabic ابراهيم ("Ibrahim"), a patriarch whose life is narrated in the [[Hebrew Bible]]/[[Old Testament]], and as a prophet in the [[Qur'an]] and also called a prophet in [[Book of Genesis|Genesis]] 20:7). |
|||
The standard text common to all of these subsequent tradition is known as the [[Hebrew Bible]], roughly the first five books of the [[Old Testament]], starting with the [[book of Genesis]] through to [[Deuteronomy]]. However, each of them added substantially different texts to their emerging canons, and hence their respective philosophical developments varied widely. |
|||
=== Jewish philosophy === |
|||
''See article'' ''[[Jewish philosophy]]'' |
|||
=== Christian philosophy === |
|||
''See article [[Christian philosophy]]'' |
|||
=== Islamic philosophy === |
|||
''See articles [[Islamic philosophy]], [[Early Islamic philosophy]], and [[Modern Islamic philosophy]]'' |
|||
Islamic philosophy as [[Henry Corbin]] describes is a philosophy whose development, and whose modalities, are essentially linked to the religious and spiritual fact of [[Islam]].<ref>Corbin (1993) p.xiv</ref> In the other word, it represents the style of philosophy produced within the framework of Islamic culture. This description does not suggest that it is necessarily concerned with religious issues, nor even that it is exclusively produced by Muslims.<ref name="Leaman">[http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/H057 Leaman, Oliver, (1998). Islamic philosophy. In E. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved December 30, 2007]</ref> |
|||
====Religious roots==== |
|||
Theoretical questions were raised right from the beginning of Islam, questions, which could, to a certain extent be answered by reference to Islamic texts such as the [[Quran]], the practices of the community and the traditional sayings of [[Muhammad]], the [[Prophets of Islam|Prophet of Islam]], and his [[Sahabah|Companion]]s.<ref name="Leaman"/> In fact, rational arguments about Islamic doctrines starts with the Quran itself, and has been followed up in the utterances of the Muhammad and especially in the sermons of [[Ali]]. This despite the fact that their style and approach are different from those of the Muslim theologians.<ref name="Motahhari">[http://www.muslimphilosophy.com/ip/kalam.htm An Introduction to 'Ilm al-Kalam] by [[Morteza Motahhari]]</ref> |
|||
Though nothing definite can be said about the beginnings of [[Kalam|theology]] among Muslims, what is certain is that discussion of some of the problems, such as the issue of [[Predestination in Islam|predestination]], [[free will]] and [[Adalah|Divine Justice]], became current among Muslims during the first half of the 2nd century of Islam coincides with 8th century. Perhaps the first formal centre of such discussions was the circle of [[Hasan al-Basri]](d.728-29).<ref name="Motahhari"/> Later several theological schools have emerged from 8th to 10th century. [[Mu'tazili]] theology originated in the 8th century in [[Basra]] (Iraq) by [[Wasil ibn Ata]] (d.748 A.D.).<ref>Martin ''et al.'', 1997</ref> |
|||
====Transferring of Greek philosophy==== |
|||
The early [[Muslim conquests|conquests of the Muslims]] brought them into close contact with centers of civilization heavily influenced by [[Christianity]] and also by [[Culture of Greece|Greek]] culture. Many rulers wished to understand and use the Greek forms of knowledge, some practical and some theoretical, and a [[House of Wisdom|large translation project]] started which saw official support for the assimilation of Greek culture. This had a powerful impact upon all areas of Islamic philosophy. [[Neoplatonism]] definitely became the prevalent school of thought, following closely the curriculum of Greek philosophy which was initially transmitted to the Islamic world.<ref name="Leaman"/> |
|||
====Periods==== |
|||
[[Henry Corbin]] has divided the history of Islamic philosophy into three periods.<ref name="Corbin">Corbin (1993), pp. xvi and xvii</ref> |
|||
=====Early Islamic philosophy===== |
|||
The first period of Islamic philosophy coincides with [[Islamic golden age]]. During this time pure philosophical thought is usually used [[Aristotelianism]] and [[Neoplatonism]] thought as its sources. But it also influenced by Islamic thought and culture. [[Abdoldjavad Falaturi|Falaturi]] has shown in his research that how Hellenistic philosophy diverged in the context of Islamic culture. On the other hand, Corbin has shown how mystic aspect of Islam, especially [[Shia]] affected philosophy. This period begins with [[al-Kindi]] and ends with [[Averroes]] (d.1198).<ref name="Corbin"/> On the other hand, there were crucial theological debates between [[Kalam|Muslim theologians]]. These discussion also helped to rise of rational debates about religion, especially [[Islam]]. |
|||
[[Avicenna]] is one of the most prominent figures of this period. He is a thinker who attempted to redefine the course of [[Islamic philosophy]] and channel it into new directions. Avicenna's metaphysical system is built on the ingredients and conceptual building blocks which are largely [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] and [[Neoplatonism|Neoplatonic]], but the final structure is more than the sum of its parts.<ref name="Iranica">{{cite encyclopedia|last= |first= | authorlink= | title=Avicenna | encyclopedia=Encyclopedia Iranica | accessdate=2007-12-30|location=|publisher=|url=http://www.iranica.com/newsite/articles/v3f1/v3f1a046.html}} |
|||
</ref> In the [[Islamic Golden Age]], due to [[Avicenna]]'s successful reconciliation between [[Aristotelianism]] and [[Neoplatonism]] along with [[Kalam|Islamic theology]], [[Avicennism]] eventually became the leading school of [[early Islamic philosophy]] by the 12th century. Avicenna had become a central authority on philosophy by then.<ref>Nahyan A. G. Fancy (2006), p. 80-81, "Pulmonary Transit and Bodily Resurrection: The Interaction of Medicine, Philosophy and Religion in the Works of Ibn al-Nafīs (died 1288)", ''Electronic Theses and Dissertations'', [[University of Notre Dame]].[http://etd.nd.edu/ETD-db/theses/available/etd-11292006-152615]</ref> |
|||
Although this school was highly criticized by Muslim theologians, such as [[al-Ghazali]], philosophers, like [[Averroes]], and [[Sufism|Sufis]], Avicenna's writings spread like fire and continued until today to form the basis of philosophic education in the Islamic world. For to the extent that the post-Averroistic tradition remained philosophic, especially in the eastern Islamic lands, it moved in the directions charted for it by Avicenna in the investigation of both theoretical and practical sciences.<ref name="Iranica"/> |
|||
=====Mystical philosophy===== |
|||
After the death of [[Averroes]], Islamic philosophy in the Peripatetic style went out of fashion in the Arab part of Muslim world, until the 19th century. [[Sufi metaphysics|Mystical philosophy]], by contrast, continued to flourish, although no thinkers matched the creativity of [[Ibn Arabi]] or [[Ibn Sab‘in]]. In the Persian-speaking part, Islamic philosophy has continued to follow a largely [[Illuminationist philosophy|Illuminationist]] curriculum, which is introduced by [[Shahab al-Din Suhrawardi|Suhrawardi]].<ref name="Leaman"/><ref name="Corbin"/> |
|||
=====Transcendent Theosophy===== |
|||
The third period, according to Corbin, begins in the 16th century after emergence of [[Safavid dynasty]] in [[Persia]].<ref name="Corbin"/> The most prominent figure of this period is [[Mulla Sadra]] who introduced [[Transcendent Theosophy]] as a critical philosophy which brought together [[Avicennism|Peripatetic]], [[Illuminationist philosophy|Illuminationist]] and [[Sufi metaphysics|gnostic philosophy]] along with [[Ash'ari]] and [[Theology of Twelvers|Twelvers]] [[Kalam|theology]], the source of which lay in the Islamic revelation and the mystical experience of reality as existence.<ref>[http://www.muslimphilosophy.com/ip/rep/H027.htm Mulla Sadra (Sadr al-Din Muhammad al-Shirazi) (1571/2-1640)]</ref><ref>Leaman (2007), pp.146 and 147</ref> This philosophy becomes dominant form of philosophy in [[Iran]] since 19th century. [[Shah Wali Allah]] extended Suhrawardi school of thought to the [[Indian subcontinent]].<ref name="Leaman"/> |
|||
=====Modern era===== |
|||
New trends have emerged during 19th and 20th centuries due to challenge of [[western philosophy]] and [[Modernity]] to traditional Islamic philosophy. On one hand some of the scholars such as [[Asadabadi|Jamal-ad-Din Asadabadi]] and [[Muhammad Abduh]] sought to find rational principles which would establish a form of thought which is both distinctively Islamic and also appropriate for life in modern scientific societies, a debate which is continuing within Islamic philosophy today. [[Muhammad Iqbal]] is one of the prominent figure of this group who provided a rather eclectic mixture of Islamic and European philosophy. On the other hand, some thinkers reacted to the phenomenon of [[modernity]] by developing [[Islamic fundamentalism]]. This resuscitated the earlier antagonism to philosophy by arguing for a return to the original principles of Islam and rejected modernity as a Western imperialist intrusion.<ref name="Leaman"/> In [[Iran]], the effects of mystic philosophers especially Mulla Sadra is great, and philosophers who are more loyal to traditional [[Islamic philosophy]] have tried to keep alive this school and use it to deal with Modernism. [[Allameh Tabatabaei]] is the most prominent figure of this group. |
|||
<ref>See: |
|||
* Leaman (2000), p.410 |
|||
* Nasr (1996), pp.324 and 325</ref> Nowadays [[Seyyed Hossein Nasr]] tries to introduce traditional [[Islamic philosophy]] and |
|||
dealt with the Islamic response to the challenges of the modern world.<ref>Fakhri (2004), p.322</ref> Finally, there have been many thinkers who have adapted and employed non-Islamic philosophical ideas as part of the normal philosophical process of seeking to understand conceptual problems such as [[Hegelianism]] and [[Existentialism]]. Therefore, modern Islamic philosophy is thus quite diverse, employing a wide variety of techniques and approaches to its subjects.<ref>Leaman (2000), p.410</ref> |
|||
=== Judeo-Islamic philosophy === |
|||
''See article [[Judeo-Islamic philosophies (800 - 1400)]]'' |
|||
== African philosophy == |
|||
{{Main|African philosophy}} |
|||
==See also== |
|||
* [[History of ethics]] |
|||
* [[List of years in philosophy]] |
|||
* [[List of important publications in philosophy]] |
|||
==Footnotes== |
|||
{{Reflist}} |
|||
==References== |
|||
{{Wikiquote}} |
|||
*{{cite book|last=Corbin|first=Henry|authorlink=Henry Corbin|title=History of Islamic Philosophy, Translated by Liadain Sherrard, [[Philip Sherrard]]|publisher=London; Kegan Paul International in association with Islamic Publications for The Institute of Ismaili Studies |year=1993|isbn=0-7103-0416-1}} |
|||
*{{cite book|last=Nasr|first=Seyyed Hossein|authorlink=Hossein Nasr|author2=Mehdi Aminrazavi|title=The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia|publisher=Routledge |year=1996 |isbn=0-7007-0314-4}} |
|||
*{{cite book|last=Leaman|first=Oliver|authorlink=Oliver Leaman|author2=Parviz Morewedge|title=Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, editor: Edward Craig |publisher=Routledge |year=2000 |isbn=0-415-22364-4}} |
|||
{{Philosophy topics}} |
|||
{{DEFAULTSORT:History Of Philosophy}} |
|||
[[Category:History of philosophy| ]] |
Revision as of 21:46, 22 March 2019
Redirect to:
This page is a redirect. The following categories are used to track and monitor this redirect:
|