Edmund Husserl
Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl (April 8, 1859 - April 26, 1938) was born into a Jewish family in Prostejov (Prossnitz) in Moravia (now in the Czech Republic). He was the founder of the phenomenological movement and a pupil of Franz Brentano and Carl Stumpf. Among others, he would influence Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. (Hermann Weyl's interest in intuitionistic logic and impredicativity, for example, seems to have been as a result of contact with Husserl.)
Life and works
Husserl's studies and early works
Husserl initially studied mainly mathematics at the universities of Leipzig (1876) and Berlin (1878) with the then famous professors Karl Weierstrass and Leopold Kronecker. In 1881 he went to Vienna to study under the supervision of Leo Königsberger (a former student of Weierstrass) and obtained his doctors degree in 1883 with the work Beiträge zur Variationsrechnung (Contributions to the Calculus of Variations).
Only in 1884 in Vienna he started following lectures by Franz Brentano on psychology and philosophy. Brentano impressed him so much that he decided to dedicate his life to philosophy. Husserl studied briefly with him and then in 1886 went to the university of Halle to obtain his habilitation with Carl Stumpf, a former student of Brentano. Under his supervision he wrote Über den Begriff der Zahl (On the concept of Number; 1887) which would serve later as the base for his first major work the Philosophie der Arithmetik (Philosophy of Arithmetic; 1891).
In these first works he tries to combine mathematics, psychology and philosophy with as main goal to provide a sound foundation for mathematics. He analyses the psychological process needed to obtain the concept of number and then tries to build up a systematical theory on this analysis. To achieve this he uses several methods and concepts taken from his teachers. From Weierstrass he derives the idea that we generate the concept of number by counting a certain collection of objects. From Brentano and Stumpf he takes over the distinction between proper and improper presenting. In an example Husserl explains this in the following way: if you are standing in front of a house, you have a proper, direct presentation of that house, but if you are looking for it and ask for directions, then these directions (e.g. the house on the corner of this and that street) are an indirect, improper presentation. In other words, you can have a proper presentation of an object if it is actually present, and an improper (or symbolic as he also calls it) if you only can indicate that object through signs, symbols, etc.
Another important element that Husserl took over from Brentano, is intentionality, the notion that the main characteristic of consciousness is that it is always intentional. While often simplistically summarised as "aboutness" or the relationship between mental acts and the external world, Brentano defined it as the main characteristic of psychical phenomena, by which they could be distinguished from physical phenomena. Every mental phenomenon, every psychological act has a content, is directed at an object (the intentional object). Every belief, desire etc. has an object that they are about: the believed, the wanted. Brentano used the expression "intentional inexistence" to indicate the status of the objects of thought in the mind. The property of being intentional, of having an intentional object, was the key feature to distinguish psychical phenomena and physical phenomena, because physical phenomena lack intentionality altogether.
Later developments
Some years after the publication of his main work, the Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations; first edition, 1900-1901) Husserl made some key discoveries, that led him to assert that in order to study the structure of consciousness, one would have to distinguish between the act of consciousness (noesis) and the phenomena at which it is directed (the noemata). Knowledge of essences would only be possible by eliminating all assumptions about the existence of an external world. This procedure he called epoché. These new concepts prompted the publication of the Ideen (Ideas) in 1913, in which they were at first incorporated, and a plan for a second edition of the Logische Untersuchungen.
From the ideen onward Husserl concentrated more and more on the ideal, essential structures of consciousness. As he wanted to exclude any hypothesis on the existence of external objects, he introduced the method of phenomenological reduction to eliminate them. What was left over was the pure transcendental ego, as opposed to the concrete empirical ego. Now Husserl's (transcendental) phenomenology is the study of the essential structures that are left in pure consciousness: this amounts in practise to the study of the noemata and the relations among them.
In a later period, Husserl shifted to a still more explicitly idealist position, which is best expressed in his Cartesian Meditations (1931).
Husserl, was eventually denied the use of the Albert-Ludwighs-Universitat library (Freiburg), as a result of the anti-Jewish legislation the National Socialist (Nazi) majority passed in April 1933. His former pupil and Nazi Party member, Martin Heidegger, informed Husserl that he was discharged. Moreover, Heidegger removed the dedication to Husserl from his most widely known work Being and Time when it was reissued in 1941.
In 1939 Husserl's manuscripts, amounting to approximately 40,000 pages, were deposited at Louvain to form the Archives Husserl. Most of the material has been published.
Bibliography
Works by Husserl
- Über den Begriff der Zahl. Psychologische Analysen (1887)
- Philosophie der Arithmetik. Psychologische und logische Untersuchungen (1891)
- Logische Untersuchungen. Erste Teil: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik (1900)
- Logische Untersuchungen. Zweite Teil: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis (1901)
- Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft (1911)
- Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie (1913)
- Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1928)
- Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft (1929)
- Mèditations cartèsiennes (1931)
- Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzentale Phänomenologie: Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie (1936)
Works on Husserl
- Rollinger, R. D. (1999). Husserl’s Position in the School of Brentano Phaenomenologica 150. Kluwer, Dordrecht. ISBN 0-7923-5684-5
- Schuhmann, K. (1977). Husserl – Chronik (Denk- und Lebensweg Edmund Husserls) Number I in Husserliana Dokumente Nijhoff, Den Haag. ISBN 90-247-1972-0
- Smith, B. and Smith, D., editors (1995). The Cambridge Companion to Husserl Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. ISBN 0521436168
External links
- www.hiw.kuleuven.ac.be/hiw/eng/husserl The Husserl-Archive in Louvain, International Center for Phenomenological Research
- www.uni-koeln.de/phil-fak/husserl The Husserl-Archive of the University of Cologne
- www.husserlpage.com "Aim: To provide easy access to those net resources pertaining to the life and work of the 20th century philosopher, Edmund Husserl."
- Husserl.info Articles, Phenomenological Directory and Bibliographies Database, Biblio Guides, Wesenschau e-Journal for Transcendental Logic and Comparative Philosophy, Phenomenological Dictionary, Phenomenological Forum
- Husserl.net Open Content Project on Husserl.