User:Ssmith95/sandbox
Linguistic Universal Draft:
Lead Edit:
A linguistic universal is a pattern that occurs systematically across natural languages, potentially true for all of them. For example, All languages have nouns and verbs, or If a language is spoken, it has consonants and vowels. Research in this area of linguistics is closely tied to the study of linguistic typology, and intends to reveal generalizations across languages, likely tied to cognition, perception, or other abilities of the mind. The field has its origins as far back as Noam Chomsky's proposal for a "Universal Grammar," but was largely formalized with pioneering work done by the linguist Joseph Greenberg, who derived a set of forty-five basic universals, mostly dealing with syntax, from a study of some thirty languages.
Though there has been significant research into linguistic universals, in more recent times some linguists, namely Nicolas Evans and Stephen C. Levinson, have argued against the existence of absolute linguistic universals that are shared across all languages. These linguists cite problems such as ethnocentrism amongst cognitive scientists, and thus linguists, as well as insufficient research into all of the world's languages in discussions related to linguistic universals, instead promoting such similarities as simply strong tendencies.
Terminology:
Linguists distinguish between two kinds of universals: absolute (opposite: statistical, often called tendencies) and implicational (opposite non-implicational). Absolute universals apply to every known language and are quite few in number; an example is All languages have pronouns. An implicational universal applies to languages with a particular feature that is always accompanied by another feature, such as If a language has trial grammatical number, it also has dual grammatical number, while non-implicational universals just state the existence (or non-existence) of one particular feature.
Also in contrast to absolute universals are tendencies (also known as statistical universals), statements that may not be true for all languages but nevertheless are far too common to be the result of chance. They also have implicational and non-implicational forms. An example of the latter would be The vast majority of languages have nasal consonants. However, most tendencies, like their universal counterparts, are implicational. For example, With overwhelmingly greater-than-chance frequency, languages with normal SOV order are postpositional. Strictly speaking, a tendency is not a kind of universal, but exceptions to most statements called universals can be found. For example, Latin is an SOV language with prepositions. Often it turns out that these exceptional languages are undergoing a shift from one type of language to another. In the case of Latin, its descendant Romance languages switched to SVO, which is a much more common order among prepositional languages.
Universals may also be bidirectional or unidirectional. In a bidirectional universal two features each imply the existence of each other. For example, languages with postpositions usually have SOV order, and likewise SOV languages usually have postpositions. The implication works both ways, and thus the universal is bidirectional. By contrast, in a unidirectional universal the implication works only one way. Languages that place relative clauses before the noun they modify again usually have SOV order, so pre-nominal relative clauses imply SOV. On the other hand, SOV languages worldwide show little preference for pre-nominal relative clauses, and thus SOV implies little about the order of relative clauses. As the implication works only one way, the proposed universal is a unidirectional one.
Linguistic universals in syntax are sometimes held up as evidence for Chomsky's proposed Universal Grammar (although epistemological arguments are more common). Other explanations for linguistic universals have been proposed, for example, that linguistic universals tend to be properties of language that aid communication. If a language were to lack one of these properties, it has been argued, it would probably soon evolve into a language having that property.
Michael Halliday has argued for a distinction between descriptive and theoretical categories in resolving the matter of the existence of linguistic universals, a distinction he takes from J.R. Firth and Louis Hjelmslev. He argues that "theoretical categories, and their inter-relations construe an abstract model of language...; they are interlocking and mutually defining". Descriptive categories, by contrast, are those set up to describe particular languages. He argues that "When people ask about 'universals', they usually mean descriptive categories that are assumed to be found in all languages. The problem is there is no mechanism for deciding how much alike descriptive categories from different languages have to be before they are said to be 'the same thing'"
Universal Grammar:
Noam Chomsky's work related to the "innateness hypothesis," as it pertains to our ability to rapidly learn any language without formal instruction and with limited input or a "poverty of stimulus," is what began research into linguistic universals. This lead to his proposal for a shared underlining grammar structure for all languages that he claimed must present somewhere in the human brain prior to language acquisition, a concept he called a Universal Grammar (UG). Chomsky defines Universal Grammar as "the system of principles, conditions, and rules that are elements or properties of all human languages... by necessity"(Citation). He states that UG expresses "the essence of human language," and believes that the structure-dependent rules of UG are what allow humans to interpret and create endless novel grammatical sentences. Chomsky asserts that UG is the underlying connection between all languages and any the various differences between languages are all relative with respect to UG. He claims that UG is essential to our ability to learn languages, and thus uses it as evidence in a discussion of how to form a potential 'theory of learning' for humans across all or many of the cognitive abilities we learn throughout our lives. The discussion of Chomsky's UG, its innateness, and its connection to how humans learn language has been one of the more written about topics in linguistic studies to date, and has left division amongst the linguists who support Chomsky's claims of UG and those who, especially in more recent years, have argued against the notion of an underlying shared grammar structure present in all languages.
Semantics:
In semantics, research into linguistic universals has taken place in a number of ways. Some linguists, starting with Gottfried Leibniz, have pursued the search for a hypothetic irreducible semantic core of all languages. A modern variant of this approach can be found in the natural semantic metalanguage of Anna Wierzbicka and associates. Other lines of research suggest cross-linguistic tendencies to use body part terms metaphorically as adpositions, or tendencies to have morphologically simple words for cognitively salient concepts. The human body, being a physiological universal, provides an ideal domain for research into semantic and lexical universals. In a seminal study, Cecil H. Brown (1976) proposed a number of universals in the semantics of body part terminology, including the following: in any language, there will be distinct terms for BODY, HEAD, ARM, EYES, NOSE, and MOUTH; if there is a distinct term for FOOT, there will be a distinct term for HAND; similarly, if there are terms for INDIVIDUAL TOES, then there are terms for INDIVIDUAL FINGERS. Subsequent research has shown that most of these features have to be considered cross-linguistic tendencies rather than true universals. Several languages like Tidore and Kuuk Thaayorre lack a general term meaning 'body'. On the basis of such data it has been argued that the highest level in the partonomy of body part terms would be the word for 'person'.
Some other examples of proposed linguistic universals in semantics include the idea that all languages possess words with the meaning '(biological) mother' and 'you (second person singular pronoun)' and statistical tendencies of meanings of basic color terms in relation to the number of color terms used by a respective languages. Though words in any given language may be polysemous, the concept that a single word may possess multiple meanings, there appears to be at least one word in every language that can be used for the meaning of '(biological) mother,' and the same can be said about 'you (second person singular pronoun). For colors, there seems to be a pattern of an implicational universal in relation to the various meanings of basic color terms with respect to the total number of words describing color. For example, if a language possesses only two terms for describing color, their respective meanings will be 'black' and 'white,' or perhaps 'dark' and 'light'. If a language possesses more than two color terms, the additional terms will follow trends related to the focal colors determined by the physiology of how we perceive color. This means that: if a language possess three color terms, the third will mean 'red', and if a language possesses four color terms, the next will mean 'yellow' or 'green', if five then both 'yellow' and 'green' are added, if six than 'blue', and so on.
Counterarguments:
Evans and Levinson are two linguists who have written against the existence of linguistic universals, making a particular mention of certain inefficiencies with Chomsky's proposal for a Universal Grammar. They argue that across the 6,000-8,000 languages there are merely strong tendencies at best, which arise primarily due to fact that many languages are connected to one another through shared historical backgrounds or lineage, an example being the subset of Romance languages in Europe that were derived from ancient Latin, and thus it can be expected that they share some core similarities. In their eyes, the linguists of the past who had proposed or supported the concepts of linguistic universals have done so "under the assumption that most languages are English-like in their structure" (citation) and after only analyzing a limited range of languages. They identify "ethnocentrism," the idea "that most cognitive scientists, linguists included, speak only familiar European languages, all close cousins in structure," (citation) as a possible influence towards the various problems they identify in the research conducted on linguistic universals. With regards to Chomsky's Principles-and-Parameters theory, these linguists claim that the explanation of the structure and rules applied to UG are either false, due to a lack of detail into the various constructions that are used when creating or interpreting a grammatical sentence, or that the theory is unfalsifiable due to these vague and oversimplified assertions made by Chomsky. Instead, Evans and Levinson highlight the diversity that exists amongst the many languages spoken around the world to promote further investigation into the many cross-linguistic variations that do exist. Their article promotes linguistic diversity by citing multiple examples of variation in how "languages can be structured at every level: phonetic, phonological, morphological, syntactic and semantic," and claims that increased understanding and acceptance of linguistic diversity over concepts of false claims linguistic universals, or better stated as strong tendencies, will lead to more enlightening discoveries in the studies of human cognition. (citation)
Unattached additional info:
![]() | This is a user sandbox of Ssmith95. You can use it for testing or practicing edits. This is not the place where you work on your assigned article for a dashboard.wikiedu.org course. Visit your Dashboard course page and follow the links for your assigned article in the My Articles section. |